[Paleopsych] Christianity Today: The "Virtue" of Lust?
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Wed Apr 27 01:25:13 UTC 2005
The "Virtue" of Lust?
http://www.christianitytoday.com/bc/2005/003/4.18.html
May/June 2005, Vol. 11, No. 3, Page 18
So says philosopher Simon Blackburn.
by W. Jay Wood
Lust by Simon Blackburn
Oxford Univ. Press, 2004, 144 pp., $17.95
Middle-aged male philosophers aren't, perhaps, the first persons one
consults about sexual pleasures and pursuits, but they have certainly
written a lot about the morality thereof. Cambridge philosopher Simon
Blackburn's book Lust, a volume in Oxford University Press' series on
the Seven Deadly Sins, is a self-consciously contrarian contribution
to that venerable genre.
Blackburn is a prolific writer of both popular and professional
philosophy, an outstanding essayist, and an insightful reviewer of
books, whose sparkling prose customarily displays philosophical skill
and evident wit. Lust doesn't lack in stylistic grace and wit, but its
ground note is a smirking satisfaction with its own provocations, and
its treatment of opposing views falls well below Blackburn's usual
standard.
At least the reader is forewarned. Blackburn announces at the outset
that he has no intention of writing a book about the sin of lust, an
intention he admirably fulfills--which may be all to the good, since
he appears to lack any developed notion of sin and, even if he has
one, he doesn't think lust qualifies as a sin. He knows quite well, of
course, what reputation religious tradition, common sense, and
ordinary language have assigned to his subject: "Lust is furtive,
ashamed, and embarrassed"; "Lust pursues its own gratification,
headlong, impatient of any control, immune to reason"; "Lust looks
sideways, inventing deceits and stratagems and seductions, sizing up
opportunities"; "Lust subverts propriety" and is "like living shackled
to a lunatic." Given this indictment, Blackburn says, it is his task
"to speak up for lust," as a kind of attorney for the defense:
So the task I set myself is to clean off some of the mud, to rescue
[lust] from the echoing denunciations of old men of the deserts, to
deliver it from the pallid and envious confessors of Rome and the
disgust of the Renaissance, to destroy the stock and pillories of
the Puritans, to separate it from the other things that we know
drag it down. ... and so lift it from the category of sin to that
of a virtue.
What exactly does Blackburn mean by lust, and why does he think it
qualifies as a virtue? His formal account describes lust as "the
active and excited desire for sexual activity." In fact, however, his
discussion encompasses far more than this, ranging widely over the
entire spectrum of matters pertaining to human sexuality, including
ancient theories about the division of the sexes, courtship customs,
birth control and, a little closer to the topic, sexual attraction,
romantic ardor, sexual desire, sexual excitement and arousal, sexual
pleasures, sexual acts, eros, and more. Indeed, the book is mistitled;
it might more appropriately have been called something like
"Philosophical Meditations on Sex" or "Simon Blackburn's Guide to Good
Sex." The irony, of course, is that Blackburn thinks he is rescuing
these pleasures from the Christians, when in fact most Christians
don't see anything wrong with anything in the above list, when pursued
appropriately. Christians don't think it was an accident that God
created us male and female, with nerve-laden genitalia, and made most
pleasurable our obedience to his command to "go forth and multiply."
While Blackburn claims that his book "is not a history of lust or even
ideas about lust," the book's 15 chapters (which include photographs
and color plates of erotic art) nevertheless unfold in roughly
historical order, treating an array of views on various aspects of
sexuality offered by Pre-Socratic Greeks, Plato, the Cynics, the
Stoics, the Manichees, Augustine, various medieval views culminating
in Aquinas, then on to Shakespeare, Hobbes, and Kant, before moving on
to moderns such as Freud, Sartre, and Nussbaum. Blackburn is right to
resist the label of history for his work, for a genuine history of
lust would not be so unrepresentative in the passages it selects for
comment nor so blatant in what it ignores. Blackburn's anti-religious
treatment of the topic makes no mention of the Song of Solomon's
erotic poetry, the sanctity of the marriage bed (Hebrews 13), or the
biblical commands for husbands and wives not to deprive one another of
sexual intimacy (1 Cor. 7). Had he made the least effort to read some
of the Puritans he is so eager to denounce, he would have discovered
that they were no prudes. Quite the contrary: with St. Paul's
admonition in mind, they regarded a spouse's neglect of his partner's
sexual needs as grounds for excommunication! References to
contemporary Christian writing about sex are also signally absent.
The longest chapter in the book, tendentiously titled "The Christian
Panic," discusses Augustine's struggles with his own powerful sexual
drives and habits, the tensions created by his Neo-Platonist and
gnostic intellectual background, and the Christian faith he embraced
as an adult. Some of Augustine's views may strike us today as strained
or severe, but when they are viewed in historical context they offer
moderating elements. After the debauched excesses of the Roman
Empire--modern sexual libertines have nothing on Caligula and
Nero--the ancient world witnessed an opposite swing of the pendulum.
As Blackburn correctly notes, the Stoics were skeptical of sexual
pleasure, and the Manichees, with whom Augustine associated for nine
years, along with some gnostic Christian cults, preached total
abstinence from sex. Tertullian and Augustine's Christian mentor,
Ambrose, sometimes sounded as though they'd prefer the extinction of
the human race to its propagation through intercourse.
Augustine strikes a moderating position amidst these extremes, his
Christian faith and fidelity to Scripture proving a corrective to the
philosophical and sectarian extremes of his day. Augustine couldn't
deny Scripture's teaching that creation is good, including God's
provision for propagation through sexual intercourse. Moreover, our
Lord having assumed a physical body, and his having been raised from
the dead and preserved from corruption, were proof that the physical
world is not evil. Jesus' blessing of the wedding at Cana, and
Scripture's other teachings about the honor of the marriage bed and
conjugal obligations between spouses, combined to correct some of the
excesses of his day. While Augustine acknowledged the good of
marriage, he certainly denied that it was the highest good, and he
remained suspicious of sexual pleasure. He counseled married couples
capable of it to abandon sexual intimacy and instead to pursue
spiritual communion with each other and with God.
Christianity and natural reason have long taught that our appetites
for food, drink, sleep, sex, and the other natural pleasure associated
with the body can be out of whack, ill-tuned, excessive, or deficient.
The unprecedented abundance of food, leisure, drink, and sexual
stimulation that contemporary Americans enjoy has neither increased
our fulfillment nor decreased the number and degree of dysfunctions
associated with these goods, as any talk show or bestseller list will
attest. Moreover, Christianity has never regarded lust, or the other
sins of appetite, as the worst of sins--though they may be among the
most common, arising as they often do in the "heat of the moment" and
without the full consent of the will (see Aquinas, Summa Theologiae,
II-II, Q. 154, art. 3). Lust can't compare in seriousness with envy,
anger, and the many species of pride, culminating in the satanic
desire to supplant God. Rather, Christianity has always taught that
our appetite for sexual pleasure, just like those for food, drink, and
sleep, needs to be tutored, trained with bit and bridle, sensitive to
the slightest touch of command, lest it rampage out of control,
dragging us helter-skelter after it.
Blackburn thinks that the highest state of sexual desire and activity
occurs amidst what he calls "Hobbesian unity," after Thomas Hobbes,
the philosopher famous for describing life in the state of nature as
"poor, solitary, nasty, brutish and short." Hobbes wrote of sexual
intimacy, which Blackburn elaborates on as a state in which sexual
partners are in a communion of body and mind, reciprocally sensitive
to each other, "responding and adjusting to each other delicately for
the entire performance," much like musicians who more or less
unconsciously adjust to each other's playing. Blackburn seems not to
grasp that the attentive reciprocity lovers achieve in Hobbesian unity
not only does not qualify as lust, it is a most happy aspect of
conjugal bliss, as those "repressed" Puritans pointed out using the
same musical metaphors long before Blackburn. One Puritan writer wrote
that married couples "may joyfully give due benevolence one to the
other; as two musical instruments rightly fitted do make a most
pleasant and sweet harmony in a well tuned consort"^[53]1 But if
Hobbesian unity is not identical to lust, neither is it necessarily
virtuous, since it might be achieved in sexual encounters with minors,
siblings, another person's spouse, sadomasochistic and homosexual
activity, and other sexual relationships Christians consider immoral.
Much as he relishes lust, Blackburn himself acknowledges that sexual
activity can go awry, and in chapter 11, "Disasters," he chronicles
some of the ways he thinks that happens. Here, he borrows heavily, but
not without some reservations, from Martha Nussbaum's paper
"Objectification," in which she lists a variety of harmful forms of
sexual involvement, including treating the other merely as a tool,
regarding the other as lacking self-determination, as lacking agency,
as something that can be bought or sold, or swapped for an object of
similar type, or as someone whose feelings needn't be taken into
account.^[54]2 Nussbaum's list is obviously meant to exclude rape,
prostitution, pornography, and unequal power relations between
partners as legitimate forms of sexual involvement. While Blackburn
acknowledges problems with producing pornography, he is not much
troubled by its consumption; if the fantasies that it stimulates "may
not be of sex at its best, ... there is little reason to deny that
they can be." He is also less condemning of prostitution than
Nussbaum, regarding it as sometimes "sad and touching rather than
wicked and sinful."
Throughout the book Blackburn praises the loss of self that occurs in
the climax of sexual ecstasy--a "frenzy" which, as he says, "drives
out thought," "takes over other cognitive functionings," and in which
the lovers, though "lost to the world," nevertheless experience one of
the highest "pleasures of exercising lust." Curiously, and I think
inconsistently, Blackburn's high regard for the loss of reason and the
self works against the very Hobbesian unity he extols as the epitome
of "good lust." Contrary to his claim that the lovers are "responding
and adjusting to each other delicately for the entire performance"
(emphasis mine), Hobbesian unity is at that "marvelous moment"
abruptly broken, the lovers now no longer mindful of each other but
utterly captive to their own bodily pleasure. Reverting to his musical
metaphor, Blackburn says, "the player is sufficiently lost in the
music to become oblivious even to the other players." At precisely the
moment their coordinated efforts should coalesce to climax, the lovers
break off their duet to go solo.
Just here Blackburn must face the criticisms of Aquinas, whose chief
objection to sexual intercourse was precisely its customary loss of
reason and self. It wasn't sexual pleasure per se Aquinas was against,
as Blackburn suggests. Indeed, Thomas writes in the Supplement to the
Summa Theologiae that just as it is not sinful to take food for
pleasure, neither is it a "mortal sin" for a husband to seek sexual
congress with his wife for pleasure (Supplement Q 49, art. 6).
According to Thomas, we do not escape venial sin, however, precisely
because reason is momentarily abandoned: "we become flesh and nothing
more" (Q 49, art. 6). Interestingly, Thomas thought this wouldn't have
happened before the Fall, where body and mind working in perfect
harmony would have made sexual pleasure even greater than it currently
is (St II-II Q 153, art. 2). Hobbesian unity, if you will, would not
have been broken, but the lovers would have been united both in body
and mind, giving and receiving with all their faculties to wonderful
climax. Once again, in delicious irony, Christians have anticipated
and upstaged their secular counterparts in treating of sexual topics.
One won't learn much about the vice of lust by reading Blackburn's
book. One would do better to consult any of the past masters of moral
character--John Cassian, Gregory the Great, Aquinas, Dante, Richard
Baxter--or contemporary authors such as Joseph Pieper, Peter Kreeft,
and Robert C. Roberts. All these authors agree that the vice of lust,
as opposed to an isolated episode thereof, is an abiding disposition
to disordered sexual appetites and behavior, typically structured by
the thought "I can be whole or happy only if I indulge and satisfy my
sexual appetites and preferences as they suit me." It is marked by
emotions such as shame, boredom, longing, aggression, and loneliness,
and finds expression in physical abuse of oneself and others,
manipulation and deceit of others for sexual gratification, predatory
and domineering behaviors, and other actions that oppose genuine love
of the other.
To paraphrase Aristotle's remarks about generosity, sexual
gratification must be pursued with the right person, for the right
reason, at the right time, and in the right way, and to the right
degree. In-house disagreements remain among Christians regarding the
appropriateness of sex that is not open to conception, between
divorced persons, or even between members of the same sex, among other
controversies. Christians also need to think carefully to determine
when healthy sexual desires and amorous inclinations veer off into
unhealthiness and sin. Unfortunately, they'll get little or no help
toward thinking Christianly about these tough and timely issues by
reading Blackburn's Lust.
W. Jay Wood is professor of philosophy at Wheaton College. He is the
author of Epistemology: Becoming Intellectually Virtuous
(InterVarsity).
1. Leland Ryken, Worldly Saints: The Puritans As They Really Were
(Zondervan, 1986), p. 44.
2. Martha Nussbaum, "Objectification," Philosophy and Public Affairs,
Vol. 24 (1995), pp. 249-91.
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list