[Paleopsych] New Yorker: Jim Holt: Say Anything: Three books find truth under cultural and conceptual assault.
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Wed Aug 24 23:02:56 UTC 2005
Jim Holt: Say Anything: Three books find truth under cultural and conceptual
assault.
http://www.newyorker.com/critics/atlarge/articles/050822crat_atlarge
Issue of 2005-08-22
Posted 2005-08-15
People have been talking bull, denying that they were talking bull,
and accusing others of talking bull for ages. "Dumbe Speaker! that's a
Bull," a character in a seventeenth-century English play says. "It is
no Bull, to speak of a common Peace, in the place of War," a statesman
from the same era declares. The word "bull," used to characterize
discourse, is of uncertain origin. One venerable conjecture was that
it began as a contemptuous reference to papal edicts known as bulls
(from the bulla, or seal, appended to the document). Another linked it
to the famously nonsensical Obadiah Bull, an Irish lawyer in London
during the reign of Henry VII. It was only in the twentieth century
that the use of "bull" to mean pretentious, deceitful, jejune language
became semantically attached to the male of the bovine species--or,
more particularly, to the excrement therefrom. Today, it is generally,
albeit erroneously, thought to have arisen as a euphemistic shortening
of "bullshit," a term that came into currency, dictionaries tell us,
around 1915.
If "bullshit," as opposed to "bull," is a distinctively modern
linguistic innovation, that could have something to do with other
distinctively modern things, like advertising, public relations,
political propaganda, and schools of education. "One of the most
salient features of our culture is that there is so much bullshit,"
Harry G. Frankfurt, a distinguished moral philosopher who is professor
emeritus at Princeton, says. The ubiquity of bullshit, he notes, is
something that we have come to take for granted. Most of us are pretty
confident of our ability to detect it, so we may not regard it as
being all that harmful. We tend to take a more benign view of someone
caught bullshitting than of someone caught lying. ("Never tell a lie
when you can bullshit your way through," a father counsels his son in
an Eric Ambler novel.) All of this worries Frankfurt. We cannot really
know the effect that bullshit has on us, he thinks, until we have a
clearer understanding of what it is. That is why we need a theory of
bullshit.
Frankfurt's own effort along these lines was contained in a paper that
he presented two decades ago at a faculty seminar at Yale. Later, that
paper appeared in a journal, and then in a collection of Frankfurt's
writings; all the while, photocopies of it passed from fan to fan.
Earlier this year, it was published as "On Bullshit" (Princeton;
$9.95), a tiny book of sixty-seven spaciously printed pages that has
gone on to become an improbable best-seller.
Philosophers have a vocational bent for trying to divine the essences
of things that most people never suspected had an essence, and
bullshit is a case in point. Could there really be some property that
all instances of bullshit possess and all non-instances lack? The
question might sound ludicrous, but it is, at least in form, no
different from one that philosophers ask about truth. Among the most
divisive issues in philosophy today is whether there is anything
important to be said about the essential nature of truth. Bullshit, by
contrast, might seem to be a mere bagatelle. Yet there are parallels
between the two which lead to the same perplexities.
Where do you start if you are an academic philosopher in search of the
quiddity of bullshit? "So far as I am aware," Frankfurt dryly
observes, "very little work has been done on this subject." He did
find an earlier philosopher's attempt to analyze a similar concept
under a more genteel name: humbug. Humbug, that philosopher decided,
was a pretentious bit of misrepresentation that fell short of lying.
(A politician talking about the importance of his religious faith
comes to mind.) Frankfurt was not entirely happy with this definition.
The difference between lies and bullshit, it seemed to him, was more
than a matter of degree. To push the analysis in a new direction, he
considers a rather peculiar anecdote about the philosopher Ludwig
Wittgenstein. It was the nineteen-thirties, and Wittgenstein had gone
to the hospital to visit a friend whose tonsils had just been taken
out. She croaked to Wittgenstein, "I feel just like a dog that has
been run over." Wittgenstein (the friend recalled) was disgusted to
hear her say this. "You don't know what a dog that has been run over
feels like," he snapped. Of course, Wittgenstein might simply have
been joking. But Frankfurt suspects that his severity was real, not
feigned. This was, after all, a man who devoted his life to combatting
what he considered to be pernicious forms of nonsense. What
Wittgenstein found offensive in his friend's simile, Frankfurt
guesses, was its mindlessness: "Her fault is not that she fails to get
things right, but that she is not even trying."
The essence of bullshit, Frankfurt decides, is that it is produced
without any concern for the truth. Bullshit needn't be false: "The
bullshitter is faking things. But this does not mean that he
necessarily gets them wrong." The bullshitter's fakery consists not in
misrepresenting a state of affairs but in concealing his own
indifference to the truth of what he says. The liar, by contrast, is
concerned with the truth, in a perverse sort of fashion: he wants to
lead us away from it. As Frankfurt sees it, the liar and the
truthteller are playing on opposite sides of the same game, a game
defined by the authority of truth. The bullshitter opts out of this
game altogether. Unlike the liar and the truthteller, he is not guided
in what he says by his beliefs about the way things are. And that,
Frankfurt says, is what makes bullshit so dangerous: it unfits a
person for telling the truth.
Frankfurt's account of bullshit is doubly remarkable. Not only does he
define it in a novel way that distinguishes it from lying; he also
uses this definition to establish a powerful claim: "Bullshit is a
greater enemy of truth than lies are." If this is true, we ought to be
tougher on someone caught bullshitting than we are on someone caught
lying. Unlike the bullshitter, the liar at least cares about the
truth. But isn't this account a little too flattering to the liar? In
theory, of course, there could be liars who are motivated by sheer
love of deception. This type was identified by St. Augustine in his
treatise "On Lying." Someone who tells a lie as a means to some other
goal tells it "unwillingly," Augustine says. The pure liar, by
contrast, "takes delight in lying, rejoicing in the falsehood itself."
But such liars are exceedingly rare, as Frankfurt concedes. Not even
Iago had that purity of heart. Ordinary tellers of lies simply aren't
principled adversaries of the truth. Suppose an unscrupulous used-car
salesman is showing you a car. He tells you that it was owned by a
little old lady who drove it only on Sundays. The engine's in great
shape, he says, and it runs beautifully. Now, if he knows all this to
be false, he's a liar. But is his goal to get you to believe the
opposite of the truth? No, it's to get you to buy the car. If the
things he was saying happened to be true, he'd still say them. He'd
say them even if he had no idea who the car's previous owner was or
what condition the engine was in.
Frankfurt would say that this used-car salesman is a liar only by
accident. Even if he happens to know the truth, he decides what he's
going to say without caring what it is. But then surely almost every
liar is, at heart, a bullshitter. Both the liar and the bullshitter
typically have a goal. It may be to sell a product, to get votes, to
keep a spouse from walking out of a marriage in the wake of
embarrassing revelations, to make someone feel good about himself, to
mislead Nazis who are looking for Jews. The alliance the liar strikes
with untruth is one of convenience, to be abandoned the moment it
ceases to serve this goal.
The porousness of Frankfurt's theoretical boundary between lies and
bullshit is apparent in Laura Penny's "Your Call Is Important to Us:
The Truth About Bullshit" (Crown; $21.95). The author, a young
Canadian college teacher and former union organizer, begins by
saluting Frankfurt's "subtle and useful" distinction: "The liar still
cares about the truth. The bullshitter is unburdened by such
concerns." She then proceeds to apply the term "bullshit" to every
kind of trickery by which powerful, moneyed interests attempt to gull
the public. "Most of what passes for news," Penny submits, "is
bullshit"; so is the language employed by lawyers and insurance men;
so is the use of rock songs in ads. She even stretches the rubric to
apply to things as well as to words: "The new product that will change
your life is probably just more cheap, plastic bullshit," she writes.
At times, despite her nod to Frankfurt, Penny appears to equate
bullshit with deliberate deceit: "Never in the history of mankind have
so many people uttered statements they know to be untrue." But then
she says that George W. Bush ("a world-historical bullshitter") and
his circle "distinguish themselves by believing their own bullshit,"
which suggests that they themselves are deluded.
Frankfurt concedes that in popular usage "bullshit" is employed as a
"generic term of abuse, with no very specific literal meaning." What
he wanted to do, he says, was to get to the essence of the thing in
question. But does bullshit have a single essence? In a paper
published a few years ago, "Deeper Into Bullshit," G. A. Cohen, a
fellow of All Souls College, Oxford, protested that Frankfurt excludes
an entire category of bullshit: the kind that appears in academic
works. If the bullshit of ordinary life arises from indifference to
truth, Cohen says, the bullshit of the academy arises from
indifference to meaning. It may be perfectly sincere, but it is
nevertheless nonsensical. Cohen, a specialist in Marxism, complains of
having been grossly victimized by this kind of bullshit as a young man
back in the nineteen-sixties, when he did a lot of reading in the
French school of Marxism inspired by Louis Althusser. So traumatized
was he by his struggle to make some sense of these defiantly obscure
texts that he went on to found, at the end of the nineteen-seventies,
a Marxist discussion group that took as its motto Marxismus sine
stercore tauri--"Marxism without the shit of the bull."
Anyone familiar with the varieties of "theory" that have made their
way from the Left Bank of Paris into American English departments will
be able to multiply examples of the higher bullshit ad libitum. A few
years ago, the physicist Alan Sokal concocted a deliberately
meaningless parody under the title "Transgressing the Boundaries:
Toward a Transformative Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravity," and then got
it accepted as a serious contribution to the journal Social Text. It
would, of course, be hasty to dismiss all unclear discourse as
bullshit. Cohen adduces a more precise criterion: the discourse must
be not only unclear but unclarifiable. That is, bullshit is the
obscure that cannot be rendered unobscure. How would one defend
philosophers like Hegel or Heidegger from the charge that their
writings are bullshit? Not, Cohen says, by showing that they cared
about the truth (which would be enough to get them off the hook if
they were charged with being bullshitters under Frankfurt's
definition). Rather, one would try to show that their writings
actually made some sense. And how could one prove the opposite: that a
given statement is hopelessly unclear, and hence bullshit? One
proposed test is to add a "not" to the statement and see if that makes
any difference to its plausibility. If it doesn't, that statement is
bullshit. As it happens, Heidegger once came very close to doing this
himself. In the fourth edition of his treatise "What Is Metaphysics?"
(1943), he asserted, "Being can indeed be without beings." In the
fifth edition (1949), this sentence became "Being never is without
beings."
Frankfurt acknowledges the higher bullshit as a distinctive variety,
but he doesn't think it's very dangerous compared with the sort of
bullshit that he is concerned about. While genuinely meaningless
discourse may be "infuriating," he says, it is unlikely to be taken
seriously for long, even in the academic world. The sort of bullshit
that involves indifference to veracity is far more insidious,
Frankfurt claims, since the "conduct of civilized life, and the
vitality of the institutions that are indispensable to it, depend very
fundamentally on respect for the distinction between the true and the
false."
How evil is the bullshitter? That depends on how valuable truthfulness
is. When Frankfurt observes that truthfulness is crucial in
maintaining the sense of trust on which social coöperation depends,
he's appealing to truth's instrumental value. Whether it has any value
in itself, however, is a separate question. To take an analogy,
suppose a well-functioning society depends on the belief in God,
whether or not God actually exists. Someone of subversive inclinations
might question the existence of God without worrying too much about
the effect that might have on public morals. And the same attitude is
possible toward truth. As the philosopher Bernard Williams observed in
a book published in 2002, not long before his death, a suspicion of
truth has been a prominent current in modern thought. It was something
that Williams found lamentable. "If you do not really believe in the
existence of truth," he asked, "what is the passion for truthfulness a
passion for?"
The idea of questioning the existence of truth might seem bizarre. No
sane person doubts that the distinction between true and false is
sharp enough when it comes to statements like "Saddam had W.M.D.s" or
"The cat is on the mat." But when it comes to more interesting
propositions-assertions of right and wrong, judgments of beauty, grand
historical narratives, talk about possibilities, scientific statements
about unobservable entities--the objectivity of truth becomes harder
to defend. "Deniers" of truth (as Williams called them) insist that
each of us is trapped in his own point of view; we make up stories
about the world and, in an exercise of power, try to impose them on
others.
The battle lines between deniers and defenders of absolute truth are
strangely drawn. On the pro-truth side, one finds Pope Benedict XVI,
who knows that moral truths correspond to divine commands and rails
against what he calls the "dictatorship of relativism." On the
"anything goes" side, one finds the member of the Bush Administration
who mocked the idea of objective evidence by declaring, "We're an
empire now, and when we act, we create our own reality." Among
philosophers, Continental poststructuralists like Bruno Latour, Jean
Baudrillard, and the late Jacques Derrida tend to be arrayed on the
anti-truth side. One might expect their hardheaded counterparts in
Britain and the United States--practitioners of what is called
analytical philosophy--to be firmly in the pro-truth camp. And yet, as
Simon Blackburn observes in "Truth: A Guide" (Oxford; $25), the
"brand-name" Anglophone philosophers of the past fifty
years--Wittgenstein, W. V. Quine, Thomas Kuhn, Donald Davidson,
Richard Rorty--have developed powerful arguments that seem to
undermine the commonsense notion of truth as agreement with reality.
Indeed, Blackburn says, "almost all the trends in the last generation
of serious philosophy lent aid and comfort to the 'anything goes'
climate"--the very climate that, Harry Frankfurt argued, has
encouraged the proliferation of bullshit.
Blackburn, who is himself a professor of philosophy at Cambridge
University, wants to rally the pro-truth forces. But he is also
concerned to give the other side its due. In "Truth," he scrupulously
considers the many forms that the case against truth has taken, going
back as far as the ancient Greek philosopher Protagoras, whose famous
saying "Man is the measure of all things" was seized upon by Socrates
as an expression of dangerous relativism. In its simplest form,
relativism is easy to refute. Take the version of it that Richard
Rorty, a philosopher who teaches at Stanford, once lightheartedly
offered: "Truth is what your contemporaries let you get away with."
The problem is that contemporary Americans and Europeans won't let you
get away with that characterization of truth; so, by its own standard,
it cannot be true. (The late Sidney Morgenbesser's gripe about
pragmatism--which, broadly speaking, equates truth with
usefulness--was in the same spirit: "The trouble with pragmatism is
that it's completely useless.") Then, there is the often heard
complaint that the whole truth will always elude us. Fair enough,
Blackburn says, but partial truths can still be perfectly objective.
He quotes Clemenceau's riposte to skeptics who asked what future
historians would say about the First World War: "They will not say
that Belgium invaded Germany."
If relativism needed a bumper-sticker slogan, it would be Nietzsche's
dictum "There are no facts, only interpretations." Nietzsche was
inclined to write as if truth were manufactured rather than
discovered, a matter of manipulating others into sharing our beliefs
rather than getting those beliefs to "agree with reality." In another
of his formulations, "Truths are illusions that we have forgotten are
illusions." If that's the case, then it is hard to regard the
bullshitter, who does not care about truth, as all that villainous.
Perhaps, to paraphrase Nietzsche, truth is merely bullshit that has
lost its stench. Blackburn has ambivalent feelings about Nietzsche,
who, were it not for his "extraordinary acuteness," would qualify as
"the pub bore of philosophy." Yet, he observes, at the moment
Nietzsche is the most influential of the great philosophers, not to
mention the "patron saint of postmodernism," so he must be grappled
with. One of Nietzsche's more notorious doctrines is perspectivism-the
idea that we are condemned to see the world from a partial and
distorted perspective, one defined by our interests and values.
Whether this doctrine led Nietzsche to a denial of truth is debatable:
in his mature writings, at least, his scorn is directed at the idea of
metaphysical truth, not at the scientific and historical varieties.
Nevertheless, Blackburn accuses Nietzsche of sloppy thinking. There is
no reason, he says, to assume that we are forever trapped in a single
perspective, or that different perspectives cannot be ranked according
to accuracy. And, if we can move from one perspective to another, what
is to prevent us from conjoining our partial views into a reasonably
objective picture of the world?
Today, Richard Rorty is probably the most prominent "truth-denier" in
the academy. What makes him so formidable is the clarity and eloquence
of his case against truth and, by implication, against the Western
philosophical tradition. Our minds do not "mirror" the world, he says.
The idea that we could somehow stand outside our own skins and survey
the relationship between our thoughts and reality is a delusion.
Language is an adaptation, and the words we use are tools. There are
many competing vocabularies for talking about the world, some more
useful than others, given human needs and interests. None of them,
however, correspond to the Way Things Really Are. Inquiry is a process
of reaching a consensus on the best way of coping with the world, and
"truth" is just a compliment we pay to the result. Rorty is fond of
quoting the American pragmatist John Dewey to the effect that the
search for truth is merely part of the search for happiness. He also
likes to cite Nietzsche's observation that truth is a surrogate for
God. Asking of someone, "Does he love the truth?," Rorty thinks, is
like asking, "Is he saved?" In our moral reasoning, he says, we no
longer worry about whether our conclusions correspond to the divine
will; so in the rest of our inquiry we ought to stop worrying about
whether our conclusions correspond to a mind-independent reality.
Do Rorty's arguments offer aid and comfort to bullshitters? Blackburn
thinks so. Creating a consensus among their peers is something that
hardworking laboratory scientists try to do. But it is also what
creationists and Holocaust deniers do. Rorty insists that, even though
the distinction between truth and consensus is untenable, we can
distinguish between "frivolous" and "serious." Some people are
"serious, decent, and trustworthy"; others are "unconversable,
incurious, and self-absorbed." Blackburn thinks that the only way to
make this distinction is by reference to the truth: serious people
care about it, whereas frivolous people do not. Yet there is another
possibility that can be extrapolated from Rorty's writings: serious
people care not only about producing agreement but also about
justifying their methods for producing agreement. (This is, for
example, something that astronomists do but astrologers don't.) That,
and not an allegiance to some transcendental notion of truth, is the
Rortian criterion that distinguishes serious inquirers from
bullshitters.
Pragmatists and perspectivists are not the only enemies Blackburn
considers, though, and much of his book is taken up with contemporary
arguments turning on subversive-sounding expressions like "holism,"
"incommensurability," and the "Myth of the Given." Take the last of
these. Our knowledge of the world, it seems reasonable to suppose, is
founded on causal interactions between us and the things in it. The
molecules and photons impinging on our bodies produce sensations;
these sensations give rise to basic beliefs--like "I am seeing red
now"--which serve as evidence for higher-level propositions about the
world. The tricky part of this scheme is the connection between
sensation and belief. As William James wrote, "A sensation is rather
like a client who has given his case to a lawyer and then has
passively to listen in the courtroom to whatever account of his
affairs, pleasant or unpleasant, the lawyer finds it most expedient to
give." The idea that a sensation can enter directly into the process
of reasoning has become known as the Myth of the Given. The late
philosopher Donald Davidson, whose influence in the Anglophone
philosophical world was unsurpassed, put the point succinctly:
"Nothing can count as a reason for holding a belief except another
belief."
This line of thought, as Blackburn observes, threatens to cut off all
contact between knowledge and the world. If beliefs can be checked
only against other beliefs, then the sole criterion for a set of
beliefs' being true is that they form a coherent web: a picture of
knowledge known as holism. And different people interacting with the
causal flux that is the world might well find themselves with distinct
but equally coherent webs of belief--a possibility known as
incommensurability. In such circumstances, who is to say what is truth
and what is bullshit? But Blackburn will have none of this. The slogan
"Nothing can count as a reason for holding a belief except another
belief" can't be right, he claims. After all, if "John comes in and
gets a good doggy whiff, he acquires a reason for believing that Rover
is in the house. If Mary looks in the fridge and sees the butter, she
acquires a reason for believing that there is butter in the fridge."
Not so fast, a Davidsonian might reply. Sensations do not come
labelled as "doggy whiffs" or "butter sighting"; such descriptions
imply a good deal of prior concept formation. What gives John a reason
to believe that Rover is in the house is indeed another belief: that
what he is smelling falls under the category of "doggy whiff."
Blackburn is obviously right in maintaining that such beliefs arise
from causal interaction with the world, and not just from voices in
our heads. But justifying those beliefs--determining whether we are
doing well or badly in forming them--can be a matter only of squaring
them with other beliefs. Derrida was not entirely bullshitting when he
said, "Il n'y a pas de hors-texte" ("There is nothing outside the
text").
Although Blackburn concludes that objective truth can and must survive
the assaults of its critics, he himself has been forced to diminish
that which he would defend. He and his allies, one might think, should
be willing to give some sort of answer to the question that "jesting
Pilate" put to Jesus: What is truth? The most obvious answer, that
truth is correspondence to the facts, founders on the difficulty of
saying just what form this "correspondence" is supposed to take, and
what "facts" could possibly be other than truths themselves. Indeed,
about the only thing that everyone can agree on is that each statement
supplies its own conditions for being true. The statement "Snow is
white" is true if and only if snow is white; the statement "The death
penalty is wrong" is true if and only if the death penalty is wrong;
and so forth. As far as Blackburn is concerned, any attempt to go
beyond this simple observation by trying to mount a general theory of
what makes things true or false is wrongheaded. That makes him, to use
his own term, a "minimalist" about truth. By reducing truth to
something "small and modest," Blackburn hopes to induce its enemies to
call off their siege.
The problem with this strategy is that it leaves us with little to
care about. If truth necessarily eludes our theoretical grasp, then
how do we know that it has any value, let alone that it is an absolute
good? Why should we worry about whether our beliefs deserve to be
called "true"? Deep down, we might prefer to believe whatever helps us
achieve our ends and enables us to flourish, regardless of whether it
is true. We may be happier believing in God even if there is no God.
We may be happier thinking that we are really good at what we do even
if that is a delusion. (The people with the truest understanding of
their own abilities, research suggests, tend to be depressives.)
However one feels about the authority of truth, there is a separate
reason for deploring bullshit; namely, that most bullshit is ugly.
When it takes the form of political propaganda, management-speak, or
P.R., it is riddled with euphemism, cliché, fake folksiness, and
high-sounding abstractions. The aesthetic dimension of bullshit is
largely ignored in Frankfurt's essay. Yet much of what we call poetry
consists of trite or false ideas in sublime language. (Oscar Wilde, in
his dialogue "The Decay of Lying," suggests that the proper aim of art
is "the telling of beautiful untrue things.") Bullshitting can involve
an element of artistry; it offers, as Frankfurt acknowledges,
opportunities for "improvisation, color, and imaginative play." When
the bullshitting is done from an ulterior motive, like the selling of
a product or the manipulation of an electorate, the outcome is likely
to be a ghastly abuse of language. When it is done for its own sake,
however, something delightful just might result. The paradigm here is
Falstaff, whose refusal to be enslaved by the authority of truth is
central to his comic genius. Falstaff's merry mixture of philosophy
and bullshit is what makes him such a clubbable man, far better
company than the dour Wittgenstein. We should by all means be severe
in dealing with bullshitters of the political, the commercial, and the
academic varieties. But let's not banish plump Jack.
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list