[Paleopsych] Reason: John Locke Lite: The strange philosophy of a left libertarian
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Fri Feb 4 14:59:06 UTC 2005
John Locke Lite: The strange philosophy of a left libertarian
http://www.reason.com/0501/cr.tp.john.shtml
5.1 [dotclear.gif]
[6]Tom G. Palmer
[7]Libertarianism Without Inequality, by Michael Otsuka, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 180 pages, $39.95
People fight about love and lucre. They also fight about labels. A
little tussle is under way right now among academic political
theorists over the label libertarian.
Advocates of massive redistribution who seek to make every property
title subject to expropriation have decided they want to be known as
libertarians. Since its hard to appropriate a label outright, theyre
willing to share it: They have taken to calling themselves left
libertarians, to distinguish themselves from right libertarians. One
of them, Philippe van Parijs, uses the term real libertarianism,
because he feels real liberty is about doing whatever you want to do,
which means you have a right to be comfortably supported by others,
even if you are able-bodied but refuse to produce anything and instead
spend all your time surfing and hanging out.
The central goal of these left libertarians is to show that one can
maintain a core commitment to what John Locke termed property in ones
personand thus can call oneself a libertarianand yet support a state
that is empowered to redistribute property on an ongoing basis in
accordance with some formula of fairness or justice.
The latest attempt to capture the libertarian label for a radically
egalitarian redistributive state is Michael Otsukas Libertarianism
Without Inequality, a collection of essays that try to reconcile
individual freedom, egalitarian redistribution, and consensual
government. (The middle section, which seems to have been added to pad
out an otherwise very thin book, attempts to defend some rather
implausible claims about criminal justice and the right to
self-defense. Since theyre not particularly relevant to the issue of
left libertarianism, Ill set them aside.) The work is an attempt to
say something interesting by exploring the authors hunches and
intuitions. It fails.
Otsuka, a reader in philosophy at University College London, was a
student of the analytical Marxist philosopher G.A. Cohen, who holds
forth at Oxford University and to whom Otsuka dedicates the book as
his teacher, mentor, comrade, friend. Cohen gained some fame for a
series of attacks on Robert Nozicks defense of free market capitalism
collected in his book Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Inequalitythat
simultaneously demonstrated Cohens flair for bizarre examples and his
weak grasp of economics and bargaining theory.
Otsuka attempts to show that the radically egalitarian redistribution
he favors is intuitively plausible if you share his intuitions (which
many people will not); that he is entitled to call himself a Lockean
after he has reformulated Lockes ideas sufficiently that they have
been fully cleansed of the regressive ideological commitments of
Lockes (and more recent) times; and that as a Lockean he is committed
to fully consensual government, so long as a nonconsensual
super-government is around to make sure that nothing bad happens.
Otsuka complains that even many of Lockes more moderate or
left-leaning interpreters have not yet provided a sufficiently
egalitarian reconstruction of his political philosophy. In other
words, Locke wouldnt agree with Otsuka, but once Otsuka has cleansed
Lockes ideas and made them sufficiently egalitarian, Otsuka can call
himself a Lockean.
Otsuka seeks to reconcile libertarian self-ownership with what he
calls a welfarist specification of the egalitarian proviso. That
proviso requires that all the unowned stuff in the world be so divided
that each person (take a deep breath) would be able (by producing,
consuming, or trading) to better herself to the same degree as you,
where betterment is to be measured in terms of welfare understood as
the satisfaction of the self-interested preferences that the
individual would have after ideal deliberation while thinking clearly
with full pertinent information regarding those preferences.
Able-bodied persons would get only a little, while the disabled would
get more, and those with very expensive tastes and little ability
would get the most, since they would need the most to satisfy their
preferences. (Of course, somebody would have to measure all those
abilities and work out how each persons ideal deliberation would
proceed, but solving such problems for every human being should be a
pretty easy task for any reasonably qualified college professor.)
This scheme is Otsukas response to Lockes proviso governing the
appropriation of unowned resources. In his Second Treatise of Civil
Government, Locke said an appropriator would have to ensure there was
enough, and as good left to meet the objection that appropriation
might be any prejudice to any other Man. In Anarchy, State, and
Utopia, Robert Nozick adopts a formulation similar to Lockes,
specifying that you may acquire previously unowned resources if and
only if you make nobody worse off than she would have been in a state
of nature in which no land is privately held. Otsuka asserts that the
alternative proviso he proposes is convincing and fair, although he
offers no reason that anyone else should find it either convincing or
fair. He seems unaware of Lockes arguments for why appropriation of
unowned resources meets Lockes proviso.
According to Locke, he who appropriates land to himself by his labour,
does not lessen but increase the common stock of mankind. For the
provisions serving to the support of humane life, produced by one acre
of enclosed and cultivated land, are (to speak much within compasse)
ten times more, than those, which are yielded by an acre of Land, of
an equal richnesse, lyeing waste in common. And therefor he, that
incloses Land and has a greater plenty of the conveniencys of life
from ten acres, than he could have from an hundred left to Nature, may
truly be said, to give ninety acres to Mankind.
The only way to satisfy Lockes proviso is to create exclusive property
rights, for the simple reason that people produce more when they can
reap the rewards, which ensures that there is more for all and thus
that appropriation is not harmful to others. Both Locke and Nozick
rely on the historical evidence that property is more conducive to
wealth production, which makes everyone better off. It seems never to
have occurred to Otsuka that there was a reason they wrote what they
wrote; its just a matter of being intuitive, plausible, fair, etc. Why
bother with history, evidence, or reasons when you can consult your
intuitions and leave it at that?
The result of Otsukas appeal to his own intuitions is an assignment of
property that would have to be changed every time its value changed
(which happens constantly in a dynamic market) and every time the
population of the world changed (which happens many times a minute).
Also, no property could be inherited, as that would be unfair. Otsuka,
like the other left libertarians, fails to distinguish between wealth
and value, which are economic concepts, and property, which is a legal
concept. Legal institutions can reassign property titles, but if
property is constantly, chaotically, and unpredictably reassigned, its
not property at all; it has no legal security.
If the way we know about changes in wealth and value is through
changes in prices, and prices are generated by exchange of secure
property titles, then eliminating the security of property would mean
there would be no way to know how wealth or value had changed. The
solution to the problem of maintaining the kind of equality Otsuka
seeks would entail eliminating the very means by which the solution
could be reached. The entire enterprise is not merely impractical; it
is self-defeating.
Libertarianism Without Inequality is a good example of the dead end so
much contemporary political philosophy has reached. Rather than being
informed by history, jurisprudence, economics, psychology, sociology,
anthropology, or even a close knowledge of classic texts, it posits
outlandish examples as the central tests of all theories. Thus Otsuka
explains self-ownership and the right to the fruits of our labor by
asking us to imagine a highly artificial society of two strangers,
each of whom will freeze to death unless clothed. Unfortunately, the
only source of material for clothing is human hair, which can be woven
into clothing. One of the two is hirsute and capable of weaving,
whereas the other is bald and incapable of weaving. Otsuka concludes
that to force the hairy one to weave his own hair into (presumably
rather uncomfortable) garments for the bald one merely to achieve an
egalitarian outcome would be a violation of the hairy ones rights.
That kind of philosophizing provides little or no useful guidance in
the world in which we live.
After affirming that full libertarianism is achieved when you can sell
your body hair to other people but the state (or someone) assigns you
your property in everything else and adjusts your shares on what, for
consistencys sake, would have to be at least a minute-by-minute basis,
Otsuka goes on to show that the kind of government he has in mind
would be radically voluntary. It would be like Nozick, man! Only
better!
Otsuka spills a lot of pixels discussing such staples of the theory of
political legitimacy as the difference between express consent and
tacit consent and whether residence constitutes consent. His approach
reads like a parody of libertarianism, according to which people might
give their consent to live in radically unequal, feudal, slavish
conditions, meaning that libertarianism (as Otsuka understands it)
would lead to truly disturbing forms of oppression. But that would be
cool, as far as Otsuka is concerned, because they would be chosen.
Otsuka brings up exit rights only to dismiss them as uninteresting. He
never tries to apply the theory of consent to interesting real-world
examples, such as condominium associations, gated communities, and
religious cloisters that have rules governing pet size, loud music,
religious observances, and so forth. (I consented to governance by my
condo association when I bought my condo. People who like large pets
would not have consented and so wouldnt live in my condo building. But
no one can put me to death if I play my music too loudly or invite my
boyfriend over for the night.) None of that for Otsuka. Instead, in
Otsukas world, people would freely choose to be governed by feudal
lords with powers of life and death over them.
After a tedious and unhelpful treatment of consent, Otsuka gives the
game away. Remember that all that free choice has to be fair to
everyone else, so your property would be constantly readjusted to
reflect the claims of others, as demanded by Otsukas proviso. That
means there would have to be constant readjustment of property claims
among people subject to different governments. There would also have
to be some adjudication of conflicts among the governments. Otsuka
therefore imagines a fluid confederation of political societies and
monities [a monity is a political society of one] that is regulated by
an interpolitical governing body. He explains:
It would be necessary for this governing body to possess limited
powers which encompass the overseeing of the drawing of the boundaries
that demarcate these societies and monities and the settling of
disputes that might arise among these parties. While the legitimate
authority of the governments of the various societies would be based
upon consent, the legitimate authority of this governing body would
not necessarily be so based. Given the disorder and chaos which would
ensue in the absence of such a governing body, all individuals would
legitimately be subject to its authorityeven those who do not consent
to it. Hence, the ideal of political societies as voluntary
associations would need to be underpinned by involuntary governance at
the interpolitical level.
In other words, Otsuka solves the problems his theory of political
legitimacy throws up by positing a nonconsensual government that would
rule over the consensual ones. That body would exercise power
legitimately because without it there would be disorder and chaos. But
legitimacy is supposed to be a solution to the problem of who has the
authority to exercise power, a problem that Otsuka simply waves away
in a footnote.
In that note, Otsuka concedes that, given this interpolitical
governing body, what I have just called the governments of what I have
just called [political] societies would not retain complete monopolies
on the powers to legislate and punish. Therefore, given my definitions
at the beginning of this chapter, we do not, strictly speaking, have
governments and political societies here. Still, he says, they are
close enough to be called that.
Libertarianism Without Inequality is kind of like a serious book, but
not really close enough to be called that.
-------------------------------------
Tom G. Palmer is a senior fellow at the Cato Institute..
References
6. http://tomgpalmer.com/
7. http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/ISBN=0199243956/ref=nosim/reasonmagazineA/
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list