[Paleopsych] New Criterion: The whys of art by Robert Conquest
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Thu Jan 27 15:55:44 UTC 2005
The whys of art by Robert Conquest
http://www.newcriterion.com/archive/23/dec04/rconquest.htm
From The New Criterion Vol. 23, No. 4, December 2004
The troubles that beset the arts, though perhaps less amenable to
diagnosis than those besetting the political and social order, may be
thought relevant to the whole question of civilization. And their
particular phenomena often seem to be melded with the attitudes one
finds in those other fields.
Changes in art and cultural history have never been easy to assimilate
to political or economic changes. But perhaps we have enough evidence
to show that particular sub-ideologies, combined with or supported by
a bureaucratic upsurge, have caused, or been associated with, what
appear to be downhill trends. Different generations naturally engender
different styles. No harm in that. Still, it can be argued that some
fashions in the field are less troublesome than others.
In an analysis of this sort, one cannot exclude subjectivity. (And
Wordsworth warned us against the "hope of reasoning [one] into
approbation"). When a writer finds spokesmen of a new generation not
susceptible to his or others' earlier work, several notions may occur
to him. First, that tastes change. Francis T. Palgrave wrote, editing
the second Golden Treasury, "nothing, it need scarcely to be said, is
harder than to form an estimate, even remotely accurate, of one's own
contemporary poets." So, to judge art and culture is indeed, in part,
to make a more subjective assessment of the aesthetics, which is of
taste. And if one asserts that a current trend or current trends are
negative, one is, of course, open to the retort that, in various
epochs, changes of taste have emerged deplored by the representatives
of earlier trends but later seen as having their own value. True, but
it is equally true that some striking and popular new art has soon
proved no more than a regrettable and temporary fad--as with the once
universally acclaimed Ossian or the German poet Friedrich Klopstock.
Moreover, our cultural people, in the sense of producers of the arts
defined as creative, are now in a strong and unprecedented
relationship with the bureaucratic or establishmentarian world
discussed earlier. (This is, paradoxically, at a time when many of
these cultural people have entered a period of what one might call
ostentatious transgressiveness, something on which indeed both they
and their state, official, and academic sponsors pride themselves.) Of
course, there is no reason to think that sections of the
intelligentsia are any sounder on the arts than they are on politics
or history. And, here again, they, as a phenomenon, form a far larger
social stratum than at any time in the past. It might be argued that,
as with the personnel of the state apparatus proper, there is now such
a superfluity of the artistically and literary "educated" class that
their very number is part of the means of coping with, and employing
part of, the product.
There comes to a point, hard to define specifically but more or less
obvious, when a regrettable general impression is unarguably
convincing--well, not "unarguably," yet beyond serious debate. Still,
an organism, or a polity, may present faults seen as lethal that are
in practice comfortably contained and do not require therapy. Nor
would one want there to be any implied use of power from outside
institutions or individuals.
Even apart from analytics, a great deal of nonsense has been talked or
written about art, or rather Art. Some reflections seem to be in
order. The question of what constitutes "art," and what distinguishes
good from less good art, is an old one. We can be certain that
humanity was creating what we call art long before the word or the
concept existed. And--a further complication--how is it that we all
accept that some Paleolithic paintings are among the best of their
kind and excel by any standards? Well, not all; there are presumably
those who are beyond such acceptance. And in considering the paintings
of Lascaux, Altamira, and elsewhere, the question arises: What did
their creators think they were doing?
Not decorating--they did not live in the caves. So why did these men
go deep into them, too deep to see, and paint by the light of cedar
wicks set in grease-filled hollow stones? Why are the hooves of many,
but not all, the cattle shown in twisted perspective?
"Magic" is a word often used of all this. But it is indisputable that
this was not the "hunting magic" found in later, and more distant,
"primitive" depictions. "Religious" is also often applied. But magic
or religious in what way? We simply don't know--but one thing seems
obvious: they did not think of their painting as something called
"art." This point was reinforced a few years ago by an interview with
a Nigerian village sculptor of some fine formal statuettes, I suppose
you would call them. Asked why he carved them, he could only reply
that this is what he did.
Thucydides tells us, quoting Pericles, that the Athenians
"philokaloumen ... kai philosophoumen," love both beauty and wisdom.
Can the modern age combine philosophy and philokaly?
One problem, nowadays, is the sort of art in which "beauty" is not
merely abandoned but replaced by a positive addiction to the
unbeautiful, or the antibeautiful. It is true that "beauty" became
sentimentalized and cosmetic from the early nineteenth century. So it
is possible that we have now broadened and deepened the idea. One can
see today, for example, the view of Verdi as among the finest; a
commentator in The New Yorker (September 24, 2001) said of a new
performance of Otello that it was astonishingly--and
unanalyzably--moving, "stripped of directorial brainstorms and
interpretive ego trips with no attempt to deconstruct or
recontextualize." But, as Joseph Brodsky noted (of Ezra Pound),
"beauty" must arise of itself and cannot just be added from outside.
When a Greek used kalos, which we conventionally translate as
"beautiful," of a city, or a weapon, or a harbor, or a virtue, we feel
that his judgment of the practical and the moral was essentially
aesthetic. But this was not so. He did not differentiate the
categories. Kalos meant, in effect, "admirable" or "fine." Similarly,
arete, which we translate as "virtue," was used of everything from a
racehorse's speed to the skills of a fighter or an orator and is
better translated simply as "excellence." In the Renaissance, there
was a natural attempt to revive this attitude with the concept of
virtù, but the distinction between goodness and beauty was already so
firmly established that reaction from it led mainly to a mere
conscious amoralism.
We, or others, have used the word "art" of a wide range of human
action (as in the Art of War, the Art of Love). All the same, we
differentiate between various skills and the value we give to each.
Even though we may speak of "trapeze art," its artistry depends wholly
on a skill. If a practitioner regularly falls, he will not be admired.
(One could argue--indeed, I would--that in our days there are
"artists" who, in effect, do regularly fall into the arena and yet do
not forfeit their prestige.) William Hazlitt, of course, wrote
similarly of Indian jugglers. On a slightly different level, I
remember in the mid-1970s watching no television but the odd opera and
Joe Montana playing for the 49ers. I was not deeply interested in
American football as such, but in seeing this combination of, I
suppose, skill and judgment... .
In the broader context, medieval Scandinavians can be cited as having
had a wide range of skills, some of them "artistic" in the modern
usage: arts, the law, the accumulated skills and experience of
brilliant shipbuilding and shipsailing, and the making and handling of
weapons. It is not that the main arts--narrative prose and gnomic
verse--required any less sophistication than those of the present day;
there were simply less of them. Fewer people were doing fewer things.
This was as true culturally as it was socially. We may feel that Earl
Rognvald of Orkney, boasting eight hundred years ago of his nine
skills--as draughts player, runner, reader, smith, skier, archer,
oarsman, poet, and harper--set a standard towards which we should all
strive. All the same, such comprehensive mastery was exceptional even
then. And nowadays, with an immense range of skills to be mastered, an
enormous spectrum of individuality seeking an ever-wider variety in
the arts, and a huge and diversely specialized volume of knowledge,
any oneness we can expect in our culture cannot possibly be that of
the centralized and unitary.
A certain amount of scientific knowledge on the part of writers is
desirable as a matter of mere literacy. We can go further and expect
some of this knowledge actually to enter imaginative literature. When
Quintilian says in the Institutio oratoria that knowledge of astronomy
is essential to a proper understanding of poets, he is describing a
culture in which some such merging of science and art applied. Yet
even if that were regained, it would be an illusion to think that we
could ever revive the full classical unity and interconnectedness of
all the fields of knowledge, when a Greek geometer could put forward
the proposition "I cannot demonstrate the properties of a triangle
without the aid of Venus."
The minds that produce and variegate our culture form part of a large
spectrum. And when we speak of art, we should be wary of certain
high-decibel voices ringing out with claims about it or about one or
another contributor to its bulk. In particular, we should beware of
some efforts truly to represent it, to stand as icons of its
significance. Pretensions to, or perhaps better seen as projections
of, high souldom, are, generally speaking, to be rejected.
"Creativity" is a well-known dazzler. And as Anthony Powell put it in
A Writer's Notebook, "It is a rule, almost without exception, that
writers and painters who are always talking about being artists, break
down at just that level." A heavy self-conscious solemnity is another
symptom. In fact, low seriousness is a mark of every epoch. Apart from
its role in silencing merited rejection, it is also to be seen as
narrowing the grasp of the arts by blocking their lighter side. Proust
noted (of Saint-Loup) that it is a philistinism to judge the arts by
their intellectual content, "not perceiving the enchantments of its
imagination that give me some things that he judges frivolous."
The more constrictive tendencies always start among a minority, an
extremely small minority, even of the artistic or literary strata.
Then, at some point, they spill over into intellectually or
aesthetically more passive, though argumentatively even more active,
personalities.
As for the art- and literature-consuming public, it is persuaded, or
even deafened, by a small stratum. The difference between the way this
has happened in the past and the way it is happening now is that this
intermediate caste has increased in number and in power, and has to
some extent adopted, or been penetrated by, the same sociopolitical
ideologies whose mental estrangement from good sense we have already
deplored.
Constant Lambert, the British conductor and composer, is recorded as
saying that even among what we would now call the high artistic
intelligentsia, it was very rare to find one who was adept or
interested in all of the arts. In what follows, we will concentrate on
literature and, more specifically, verse. The examples given here
could certainly be matched in other fields, but should suffice for our
purposes.
Anthony Burgess said flatly that "Art begins with craft, and there is
no art until craft has been mastered." There are several ways, in
writing, as in the other arts, in which the decoupling of craft and
art may be accomplished. Explosively intended phrases tend to distract
attention from any broader pattern. But a less sensational shift of
direction may also serve, if a mood is created or titillated without
concern for anything accomplished. As Dr. Johnson said of James
Macpherson's supposed translation of the poetry of Ossian, "Sir, a man
might write such stuff forever, if he would abandon his mind to it."
One new phenomenon of our time was the establishment of English
schools and departments in the universities at about the same time as
"modernism" arose. For the first time, we had a specific and separate
group that was supposed to be exceptionally qualified to judge
literature, as against that larger, more heterogeneous set of people
constituting the cultural community. Literature was moreover beset by
theory, and in general by an excess of academicism and
discussionizing. As in other fields, many were and are simply misled
by words. A local paper speaks of those "eating the menu instead of
the meal." Academic critics claimed to be the only ones competent to
discuss poetry properly and indeed to prescribe its forms, methods,
and contents. This is as if a claim should be put forward that only
professors of ballistics should discuss cricket or football. The
American poet Karl Shapiro remarked that though he knew scores of
poets, he almost never heard from them the adulation of Eliot that is
found in the textbooks.
The past had dictatorial critics, but these have always been the more
troublesome to the degree that they were systematic. No doubt, then
and now, nondogmatic criticism contains a congeries of more or less
unconscious assumptions. But that is not the same thing, just as those
people are wrong who say that conscious and systematic political
indoctrination is all right since in any case we are subject to
unsystematic indoctrination in the set of assumptions implicit in our
society.
The answer is that a supposedly full and conscious conceptualization
is, even in so far as it may be successful at all, a narrower and
shallower matter than the other; that it goes with an authoritarian
attitude; that its products, because of the formality of their
definition, are more solidified and less able to evolve. Just as it is
those people who think they have discovered the laws of history who
have, in our time, caused our major public catastrophes, so, in a
lesser field, it is those who think they have discovered the laws of
literature who have been the trouble.
But it should also be said that there is an element of illusion in
these conceptualizations. Since it is impossible to achieve the
pretended rigor, an element of unconscious prejudice after all
remains; in fact, it is corrupted through repression and
rationalization into something less, rather than more, rational. The
more "rigor," the greater the belief that what is "rigorously" covered
is the main and major matter, while in reality, it may simply be that
part of the subject most susceptible to analysis. Obscurer but
profounder aspects of a work then tend to be forgotten.
We may also feel that the bringing to the analytic consciousness of
all one's attitudes to a piece of writing, even if it were possible,
is not an unmixed advantage. A psyche that is entirely conscious (or
with a subconscious component subject to instant recall) does not seem
to be in accord with the present design of Homo sapiens; even if an
android with these characteristics could be produced, one suspects
that it might not be wholly satisfactory. To put it in terms of the
arts, we might consider A. E. Housman's view that poetry finds its way
"to something in man which is obscure and latent, something older than
the present organization of his nature, like the patches of fen which
still linger here and there in the drained lands of Cambridgeshire."
The rules of these profound and intricate unconscious activities are
probably in practice unknowable. At any rate, if not unknowable, much
of their working is at present unknown. If the vague, peripheral, and
hypothetical knowledge we have is given the status of law, we are
worse off than before.
Literature exists for the ordinary educated man, and any literature
that actively requires enormous training can be at best of only
peripheral value. Moreover, such a style in literature produces the
specialist who knows only about literature. The man who knows only
about literature does not know even about literature.
Common in all academic circles is the assumption that argument put
forward with careful definition and meticulous analysis is
automatically superior to more general argument in more ordinary
language. The analyst is inclined to assume that anyone who is content
to use such more general formulae does so because he is incapable of
finding distinctions, untrained in the minutiae of new methods of
analysis, and in general all thumbs. And he even feels perhaps that he
has demolished a large-scale argument by dissecting, qualifying, and
distinguishing, i.e., proving that there is more to be said. This is
rather like a microscope trying to refute a telescope. It is basically
an error about semantics. Language is capable of being used in either
way, and neither is intrinsically superior to the other--as long as
the operator is aware of what he is doing, and the method is suitable
to the material. We find, in fact, that a general treatment, without
pretense of finality but rather, as it were, open-ended, is the
preferable approach to literature.
One also sees it argued that the more one knows about a work of art,
the better one is equipped to judge it aesthetically. In theory, this
sounds all right. But even if we neglect the fact that much critical
"knowledge" of a poem is in effect not knowledge at all but patterns
imposed on the poem by the critic, a little common sense will tell us
that things are not as easy as all that. Are we really to suppose that
a modern expert on painting, able to analyze brushwork with a
microscope and to identify the chemicals used, is a better judge of
painting than were the great patrons of the Renaissance? Knowledge
does not necessarily imply judgment. All truly critical, as against
technical, argument is either intuitive or hypothetical or partial.
This cannot be compensated for by a study of the raw material, however
exhaustive.
The first great age of analytical criticism, the Alexandrian, produced
among its frigidities some of the aberrations we have today--its brand
of concrete poetry, for example, of which Henry Fuseli wrote: "The
wing, the harp, the hatchet, the altar of Simmias were the dregs of a
degraded nation's worn-out taste." But it is easy to see how the
critical temper may promote meaningless drivel. One of superb
Rimbaud's worst poems is the sonnet in which he allots various colors
to the vowels. Critics were instantly found to give coherent
interpretations (eight or ten were propounded in all), though, as Paul
Verlaine tells us, Rimbaud "se foutait pas mal si A était rouge ou
vert." But his "Sonnet des Voyelles," just because it was
interpretation fodder, became the favorite and most quoted of the lot.
That was in primitive times, when criticism had not yet reached its
zenith. Still, even nowadays, the most ambiguous (or
complicated-appearing) poetry often pleases the critic best. Whereas,
in any reasonable sense, the more incomprehensible the poem, the worse
it must be.
It also seems to be felt that emotionalism proves emotion, and that
nonsense is aesthetically preferable to sense. Things have changed
since Sophocles was able to establish his sanity in old age by
reciting to a court the newly written Colonus. I cannot feel that the
point is irrelevant, any more than is Coleridge's unforgettable remark
about Shakespeare that "his rhythm is so perfect, that you may be
almost sure that you do not understand the real force of a line, if it
does not run well as you read it."
It seems odd that a taste for involved intellectualism in literature
should so often be accompanied, or succeeded, by a taste for the most
extreme irrationalism. The writer A. G. Macdonell, reviewing novels in
the mid-1920s, noted such a change in the titles: "Slashing" ones like
Rat-Ridden, Bilge-Bestank gave way to a more "Shadowy" lot, like And
She Said So Too. But on second thoughts, it will be seen that this is
natural: the two approaches both involve, in most cases, contrivance,
in its shallowest sense. We think of art from the intellect as clear,
arid, formal. Obviously, this is not always so: anything, however
emotionalist, which is devised to suit a conscious scheme is
intellectual, in this bad sense. Hysteria is the product of frigidity,
not of passion. Both extreme cases are often, it will be noted,
missionary types: the one of a highly organized and ritualistic set of
sacramental forms, the other of a theology of revivalist self-abandon.
In either case, a sectarianism.
One finds a political element, or at any rate a political tone, in
these literary discussions--with an occasional lack of amenity. How
George Orwell would have relished Anthony Hecht telling (in the
introduction to his Melodies Unheard) of opponents of meter and rhyme
that "one such radical has recently affirmed" that anyone that
observes such constraints "is unambiguously a fascist."
One of the ways to give the impression of an aesthetic performance to
those lacking the organ of taste is indeed to put into a work of art
the political, religious, or other extraneous satisfactions popular
with one or another audience. Particularly, of course, if strongly
held. As Paul Valéry wrote, "Enthusiasm is not an artist's state of
mind."
Few poets have had much experience of the political. They have
generous impulses, no doubt, and concern for humanity. These can be
expressed in various ways and are not sufficient for a poem involving
facts. On political issues, it is extremely rare for the facts to be
so clear, and the human involvement so direct and simple, as to
approach the immediacy and undeniability of experience. Still, there
can be few comments as inept as that of William Carlos Williams, in
his introduction to Allen Ginsberg, that this Beat poet had gone "into
his Golgotha, from that charnel house, similar in every way, to that
of the Jews in the past war."
Not that even those few poets with some political knowledge and
experience find it easy to produce political poems. Lawrence Durrell,
one of those few, has dealt directly with political events in prose,
in Bitter Lemons. But in the poem which concludes this book, as soon
as he approaches the subject, he has the modesty, a sense of the
subject's intractability, to write: "Better leave the rest unsaid."
Excellent advice, for several reasons.
There is an idea that expressing any reputable sentiment or opinion on
politics makes good verse. No. In particular, apart from satire, there
is almost no good political verse in English (except for Andrew
Marvell's "Horatian Ode"). J. C. Furnas in his book on--and
against--slavery, The Road to Harper's Ferry, says, "Blake, Cowper,
Wordsworth and Southey, when touching on slavery, wrote drivel." I
have come across one good poem about the nuclear bomb--by the Irish
poet Thomas Kinsella (not a "political" sort of poem, actually). None
of the hundreds on the death of Dylan Thomas is any good (and please
don't let us speak of Princess Diana). On AIDS, there are a few good
poems by Thom Gunn--a great exception.
Back in the first and second decades of this century, there was indeed
a ferment of revolutionary-sounding attitudes, and these attracted
precisely some of the aesthetically radical--Marinetti into Fascism,
Mayakovsky into Bolshevism. Enmity of artists to "capitalism" and the
"bourgeoisie" is a symptom of this radical temperament. Of course, the
notion that capitalism is hostile to art is in itself absurd. In fact,
capitalist or bourgeois patronage has often marked a great flowering
of art: the Medicis, Venice, and Holland, or, to go further back, the
great merchant republic of Athens.
The Mexican painters like Diego Rivera well illustrate one aspect of
political modernism. And it is clear that an important part of the
impact of their "new" art was due far more to the political type of
content than to the quasi cubism involved in the forms chosen. In the
palace at Chapultepec, one may see romantic revolutionary paintings of
a century ago, showing liberators like Benito Juárez and Porfirio Díaz
cursing venomous foes, etc., to the applause and enthusiasm of
romantically conceived peasants and of "the people" in general. The
difference between these and the more modern Mexican paintings is not
great, and indeed the later generation owes a good deal not merely to
this political inheritance but also to an element of primitivism
already to be seen in the work of their predecessors.
In fact, art with a revolutionary political component is very much a
traditionalist form. The only exception I have come across, where a
genuine new impulse seems visible, is in the strange statuary of
Kemalist Turkey, with its earthy New Turks pushing up out of the soil.
Here, perhaps, novelty may be due to a total lack of previous
representational art. On a slightly different point, one of the truly
remarkable things about the Mayan cities--Uxmal, in particular--is
what one may (inadequately) call the elegance of the shapes and
dispositions of the buildings (in a way like the Greek equivalent).
Literature is written in language. That language has a close
relationship to common speech. To "heighten" speech is not in fact to
depart from it more than very slightly. When poetry goes bad, from the
point of view of language, it is invariably due to the creation of
"poeticism"--a vocabulary, or diction, or general phraseology of an
isolated type. This has usually in the past taken the form of certain
words becoming traditional in poetry at the same time as they became
obsolete in common speech. But it is also possible--and this is the
form the vice took in the twentieth century--to depart from the true
roots by creating linguistic forms equally separated from the natural
language and equally to be regarded as poeticisms.
We distinguish poetry from prose. There are poetry magazines, poetry
anthologies, and so on that may print the occasional confessedly
"prose poem," but their contents and claims, generally speaking,
differ from what is usually designated "prose." So it seems that
poetry is a particular art and, presumably, in some sense a particular
craft. Traditionally, prosody sought, as Baudelaire put it, "the
immortal needs of monotony, of symmetry and of surprise"; or, if we
need an English equivalent, there is Dr. Johnson's "To write verse is
to dispose syllables and sounds harmonically by some known and settled
rule--a rule however lax enough to substitute similitude for identity,
to admit change without breach of order, and to relieve the ear
without disappointing it."
Of course, there has long been within or adjacent to such verse a
subordinate or complementary tradition of something closer to prose,
but this was always, until recently, peripheral to and dependent on
the main tradition. Even in Johnson's time, his friend Christopher
Smart, whose "Song to David" is a fine example of a long, wholly
formal poem, also wrote that fine, free apostrophe to his cat
Jeoffrey. To some extent based on the psalms, or on a sort of loose or
resolved hexameter, this genre was often not even that, but better
seen as declamation. Clearly some of this what we might call
declamatory verse is successful.
But after all, prose too may be typographically broken up into lines
for some particular effect. We have the notes from which Churchill
made his speech to a secret session of the House of Commons in 1940.
After quoting a call to man Britain's defenses and resist the then
threatened German landings, the notes go on:
That will play its part;
but essence of defence of Britain
is to attack the landed enemy at once,
leap at his throat
and keep the grip until the life is out of him.
This might, in some sense, be called an art, perhaps of rhetoric. But
in what sense is it prose? At any rate, it shows how the two arts meet
at a not readily definable point.
It can be brilliantly used: for example, in the tenser and more
dramatic passages of David Jones's magnificent In Parenthesis, the
best book produced by World War I (though we may note that Jones did
not call his work poetry but just a "writing"). It has produced
terrible stuff too: Martin Tupper, highly respected in mid-Victorian
times, is an example.
Freeish verse has been with us for some generations (when I was young,
my sister's school magazine was full if it). Most poets of this
century have written it, sometimes only rarely. Again, successes are
possible, though uncommon--Robert Frost compared writing free verse to
playing "tennis without a net"--and again, it depends for its effect
on being under the protection of the guns of the main tradition.
Modernism, in the broadest sense, was largely an import from France,
starting with impressionism. As Anthony Powell commented in A Writer's
Notebook, it is extraordinary that "after Turner, Impressionism seemed
altogether new; and `modern poetry' after Browning." (Indeed, most of
the tropes of symbolism, for example, are to be found in Shakespeare.)
But the new artistic evolution seems to have been that French models
impressed those who wrote in English. But the French had quite a
different history.
Which may remind us that there was also an element, and often a very
attractive one, of joking in the early Paris's avant-garde. And
further West, one finds the saving note of the comic not only in E. E.
Cummings but also in Dylan Thomas, for example (even at his most
portentous, he seems to fit Lautréamont's description of Byron,
"L'hippotame des jungles infernales": more sympathetic, even as a
monster, than the tyrannosaurs later infesting Bohemia).
Stéphane Mallarmé, the true avatar of symbolism, wrote specifically of
the new "dissonances" that the background of "strict" verse is needed
to make them "profitable." This sensible rule was not (and is not)
observed. And the "experimentation," as Mallarmé suggests, went beyond
the technical into the whole approach, when every sort of grammatical,
structural, and semantic novelty was tried out. Certain benefits
resulted--acceptable variations in structure, half rhymes. It was no
less a product of classicism than when Edward Gibbon himself spoke of
the alternative aims of poetry being to "satisfy, or silence, our
reason."
The crux, the main and major disjunction in all fields, was when the
artist took the decision to abandon the laity. As Pasternak wrote
later, "All this writing of the Twenties has terribly aged. They
lacked universality. I have never understood these dreams of a new
language, of a completely original form of expression. Because of this
dream, much of the work of the Twenties which was stylistic
experimentation has ceased to exist."
In fact, many writers classed as modernist were merely modern. Which
is not to say that they were not affected by experimentalism proper,
to various degrees. But with this notion of artistic alienation came
the similar, but logically distinct, element of the existential human
in his condition; and with the twentieth century, though deriving from
earlier thought, came angst.
It may be argued that artistic alienation had been around for
generations, ever since the "superfluous man" of Mikhail Lermontov,
the Byron of Continental imagination, the romantic idea of the mad or
maddish poet grandly isolated from the rest of mankind. As W. H. Auden
put it, nearly two generations ago:
Chimeras mauled them, they wasted away with the spleen,
Suicide picked them off, sunk off Cape Consumption,
Lost on the Tosspot Seas, wrecked on the Gibbering Isles
Or trapped in the ice of despair at the Soul's Pole.
In any case, when we look back, we can surely say that the great
revolution modernism thought it was bringing about simply failed.
Yet that is not the whole story. First of all, even if they were not
as world-shaking as they imagined, they might still have left us some
valuable, if peripheral, work. Such a modest contribution, after all,
is all that Mallarmé claimed--that for his classical verse was "the
great nave of the `basilica' French poetry," while vers libre simply
created special attractions on the sidelines.
Lionel Trilling noted how a contrary demand excessively catered to in
his time was for verse that advertised itself as being under high
pressure. Some verse of that type may indeed be successful. But mere
groaning and sweating and thrashing around, with adjectives to suit,
simply begs for D. J. Enright's comment: "the effects may be striking
but they don't strike very deep." And this is, or can easily become,
bad taste--as Wordsworth put it, a "degrading thirst after outrageous
stimulation." Nor will it do to attribute this sort of thing to a more
"primitive"--and therefore more true and real--depth of feeling. Yet,
as I write, I come across a poetry reviewer in the Economist praising
"a raw vigorous celebration of instinctive animal energy." (The cave
paintings, too, were subtle and civilized compared with what is now
exhibited at the Royal Academy.)
Much has been published over the past decade or two that has something
of the appearance of form, but relaxed, or dissolved, to the degree
that it is really no more than an overextended type of free verse. We
have indeed noted that this can also be said of verse reaching us from
the other pole of arid academicism. There are, of course, many people
on all sides who are in one way or another interested in poetry but
not for poetical reasons.
Kingsley Amis once wrote me, "The trouble with chaps like that is that
they have no taste--I don't mean bad taste, just the mental organ that
makes you say This is bloody good or This is piss is simply missing,
and they have to orientate themselves by things like `importance' and
`seriousness' and `depth' and `originality' and `consensus' (=
`trend')."
Even if its proponents did not say that all obscurity is profound--and
some came near to saying that--they certainly implied that all
profundity is obscure. But a muddy puddle may pretend to any depth; a
clear pool cannot. Coleridge writes somewhere that he read one of
Dante's shorter poems every year for ten years, always finding more in
it. This did not mean that it lacked comprehensibility at first
reading, merely that in this comprehensibility there were resonances
that did not immediately declare themselves.
This "death of the past" includes ignorance of the cultural knowledge
that would have been taken for granted from Chaucer to Auden. One
example: Byron's "The Isles of Greece" required some, though not much,
background. The assumed historical knowledge in the lines "A king sate
on the rocky brow/ Which looks o'er sea-born Salamis"--not even
knowledge, only literacy--is now largely forgotten (and the oddity of
"Salamis" pronounced as if the plural of an Italian sausage might have
been avoided by a parallel grip on scansion).
More generally, how widespread is this anticultural plague? I was
talking to an aging and not in the least anti-intellectual Los Angeles
businessman. He said that he had been schooled, and honed, in a
certain ambience of the old anthologies (The Golden Treasury, The
Oxford Book of English Verse) and other such inheritances, but that
his children, still less his grandchildren, no longer seemed to have
this access.
In the 1990s, television carried a replay of the 1940s Western movie
My Darling Clementine, in the course of which a traveling actor
playing Hamlet is terrorized by bad guys in a saloon, who make him
stand on a table, shoot at bottles behind him, and order him to act
something. He starts, "To be or not to be," but dries up. Doc Holliday
comes in and finishes the speech for him. This shows that half a
century ago Hollywood producers thought that all this would be
acceptable and comprehensible to the movie public. In the intervening
years, a generation has been miseducated, as we all know, in many
different ways. And one of these is that there is (or so it seems) no
longer a general memory not only of meter and rhyme but also even of
their earlier existence. Craft, it might be said, has been painted
into a corner.
There are indeed many voices, including young ones, that have called
for and started a return to verse. The persistence of form and rhythm
and rhyme in the general population, as in country music, is perhaps a
sign of their ineradicability. And "light verse" has been, on the
whole, a bastion of form.
It is true that a decline in the craft of verse has been noted before.
Edmund Wilson's "Is Verse a Dying Technique?" appeared in the late
1920s. Still, the then wave of free verse was only a peripheral
fashion. We were not simultaneously untaught the older poets. And
there were no creative-writing classes, and few experimental-academic
versifiers, or, at any rate, far fewer and less obtrusive than today.
Over the ages, the condition of the arts has been seen as a part--a
striking and important part--of the exercise of the critical
imagination, of the human mind, in their broader compass. And the
record of those faculties has seen contractions and contortions as
well as periods of progress.
Will the humanities nevertheless prosper? Such a view perhaps
underestimates, as ever, the power of inertia and interests. In
Anatole France's Thaïs, faced with the (to him) irrational spectacle
of a Pillar Saint--up on his pillar--the Roman governor's secretary
says, "There are forces, Lucius, infinitely more powerful than reason
and science." "Which?" "Ignorance and madness"--and the saint was an
"educated" man. Moreover, his views were to conquer. In Rudyard
Kipling's words:
And they overlaid the teaching of Ionia
And the Truth was choked at birth
... to rise again many years later.
Let us hope for the best.
_________________________________________________________________
Robert Conquest, author of Reflections on a Ravaged Century and The
Great Terror, is a Fellow of the Hoover Institution at Stanford
University.
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list