[Paleopsych] TLS: John Gray: The tragic view
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Tue Jun 7 21:18:25 UTC 2005
John Gray: The tragic view
The Times Literary Supplement, 97.9.26
http://the-tls.co.uk/archive/story.aspx?story_id=2089093&window_type=print
MAX WEBER. Politics and the spirit of tragedy. By John Patrick
Diggins. 334pp. HarperCollins. £20. - 0 465 01750 9.
Max Weber could scarcely fail to have a formative influence on the
development of social thought in the United States. As one of
sociology's founding thinkers, he set the intellectual agenda for
social scientists everywhere. Yet Weber's view of politics and society
has had few echoes in American intellectual life. It is too
disenchanted a vision to be accepted in a society begotten in the
faith that it is exempt from the tragic conflicts that have marked
political life throughout history. For Weber, conflicts of values are
the engine of history and politics. The task of politics is not to
achieve an ideal harmony among social goods. It is to sustain a
precarious coexistence between irreconcilable ideals and interests.
Skilful leadership can mediate conflicts of values; but they can never
be finally resolved. The vocation of politics is tragic, because no
such balance is ever achieved without irreparable loss. Political life
will always remain a realm of warring gods.
Weber's view that the intractable conflicts and murky settlements of
politics are not marks of a phase of historical development that may
soon be transcended, but permanent features of human experience, has
never been accepted in the United States; it has proved even less
digestible there than the stoical doctrines of Sigmund Freud.
Psychoanalysis was assimilated into American culture by being made to
serve self-realization rather than - as Freud surely intended -
resignation. Weber's thought has proved resistant to such a
denaturing.
In Max Weber: Politics and the spirit of tragedy, John Patrick Diggins
contrasts Weber's understanding of politics with "an American
political culture almost innocent of irony and tragedy". At the same
time, he suggests that Weber's thought has analogues in American
literature, and in the thinking of Abraham Lincoln about the choices
engendered by the Civil War. Though it encompasses an illuminating
account of Weber's life, Diggins's book is not a biography of Weber,
nor is it an analysis of his sociological writings. It is an extended
meditation on the bearings of Weber's thought on American life, using
as its primary evidences Weber's responses to the historical
circumstances of his time. Together with other interpreters, Diggins
maintains that Weber's view of the conflicts of modern society was
shaped by the understanding of tragedy which he appropriated from the
work of Nietzsche and Simmel and by the account of the limits of moral
responsibility he derived from his studies of Calvinism.
Weber's recurrent theme, of the disenchantment of human experience in
modern societies, expressed a conception of the inherent limitations
of the rational and moral exercise of power that Diggins plausibly
argues is Calvinist and Nietzschean in origin. For Weber, the spread
of rational calculation throughout society is an undoubted good, in
that it enables human wants to be satisfied more effectively; but it
is also a cultural and moral hazard, since it drains social life of
significance and subjects human beings to the meaningless demands of
efficient administration. Weber thought this an antinomy that no new
political dispensation could hope to elude. Like his disciple Joseph
Schumpeter, he had no hopes of Soviet Communism, and reacted with
incredulous contempt to suggestions that American capitalism could
escape the ironies all modern societies are fated to endure.
Throughout Diggins's carefully crafted account of Weber's life and
thought, he compares and contrasts Weber's views with those of the
principal interpreters of the American condition, particularly
Tocqueville. He records Weber's cool comment on Tocqueville's thesis
of the danger of a democratic tyranny of the majority in the United
States - that it presupposes that the fiction of popular government
will some day become a fact of American political life: which is an
impossibility. Weber shared Tocqueville's belief that the intensity of
commercial competition in the United States owes much to the pervasive
American illusion of equality; but he had no fear that egalitarian
levelling would ever become a reality in the United States. Wiser and
more prescient than Tocqueville, Weber expected that new inequalities
would arise in the United States that were immune from accountability
and control by democratic institutions. He anticipated that these new
inequalities would be legitimated as inevitable by-products of the
rational allocation of resources in free markets.
It is surprising that Diggins fails to note how strikingly Weber's
expectations have been corroborated by the growth of economic
inequality in the United States over the past twenty years. Average
incomes have fallen in the United States during a period of virtually
uninterrupted growth in productivity and national wealth. Yet the
realities of growing economic inequality have been effectively removed
from the agenda of American politics. The issues of economic justice
and social cohesion raised by widening inequalities have been
addressed only by maverick politicians, such as Ralph Nader and
Patrick Buchanan, who have been swiftly marginalized. Diggins follows
the course of recent American politics by side stepping these issues
and focusing on the multicultural politics of identity and
entitlement. As a result, the eminently Weberian conjunction in
contemporary America of enhanced economic inequalities with a
political culture of rational management goes unexamined.
Diggins rails against "the contemporary cult of multiculturalism",
which practises "a politics of institutional infiltration on the part
of minorities that have nothing to lose but their grievances",
resulting in a "return to a pseudo-aristocratic politics of privilege
based on inherited rights by reason of birth". Yet the most
distinctive trend of late twentieth-century America is not the
separation of social groups by race promoted by some advocates of
multiculturalism. It is the segregation of racial groups by economic
class. In this, the United States resembles some Latin American
countries, especially Brazil, more than it does any European country.
Diggins refers to racial and ethnic conflicts in America today as if
they were the results of mistaken multicultural doctrines rather than
a consequence of the confluence of ethnic and racial with economic
divisions. In neglecting this ominous prospect for the trifling
commotions of multiculturalism, Diggins passes over one of the most
arresting applications of Weber's thought. In a more consistently
Weberian perspective, ethnic and racial conflicts can be understood as
expressing divisions in American society in which economic
inequalities and cultural identities have become fatefully
interlocked.
One of the most interesting aspects of Diggins's book is his
exploration of the political sensibility he finds in Abraham Lincoln,
and the contrast he identifies between Lincoln's outlook and that of
Woodrow Wilson. He interprets Lincoln's ethical and political outlook
as being, like Weber's, tragic and antinomic. It was concerned with
achieving a provisional settlement among equally legitimate but
inherently opposed moral claims, rather than with the attainment of an
ideal condition in which their incompatibility was somehow overcome.
Diggins finds parallels between Lincoln's admission during the Civil
War that he was willing to tolerate slavery in order to preserve the
Union and Weber's defence of a morality of responsibility in his
famous address, "Politics as a Vocation". (In an interesting footnote,
Diggins compares Weber's view of morality with the account of
rationally incommensurable values developed in the writings of Isaiah
Berlin.) In Woodrow Wilson, Diggins recognizes an unthinking moral
absolutism that could scarcely be further removed from the acceptance
of insoluble ethical dilemmas that characterized Lincoln and Weber. He
observes that the principle of national self-determination which
Wilson invoked to determine the terms of peace after the First World
War articulated a states-rights tradition that derived from Wilson's
Virginia roots. It had not laid the basis for peace in the United
States, but instead led to the Civil War. This is an irony worth
pondering, but notably subdued in American reflection.
The paradox whereby a principle commonly believed to be progressive
and liberating had its origin in the defence of slavery is occluded in
the dominant tradition of American political thought - the liberal
progressive tradition of Jefferson, Wilson and Dewey. Diggins tells us
that there is another tradition of American thought, beginning with
Calvinism and articulated in the speeches of Abraham Lincoln and the
writings of Herman Melville and Reinhold Niebuhr, that is more
receptive to these ironies. He is ingenious in detecting affinities
between Weber's Nietzschean affirmation of antinomies in politics and
the insights of Lincoln, Melville and Niebuhr into the contradictions
of ethical life.
The argument that these disparate figures constitute an American
tradition of tragic political thought remains deeply unpersuasive.
There are worlds of difference between Melville's experimental
nihilism, Lincoln's pragmatic recognition of the political limits of
ethical reasoning, and Niebuhr's Calvinist conviction of original sin.
Diggins's thoughtful and pioneering book is weakened by the claim that
these fascinating but ill-assorted figures exemplify an American
tradition of antinomic thinking about ethics and politics akin to that
which he rightly discerns in Weber. Such a far-fetched claim can only
confirm the truth of Diggins's belief that the thought of Max Weber
has yet to find a proper hearing in the United States.
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list