[Paleopsych] TLS: John Gray: Rights are not enough
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Sat Jun 11 20:47:03 UTC 2005
John Gray: Rights are not enough
The Times Literary Supplement, 99.1.22
http://the-tls.co.uk/archive/story.aspx?story_id=2098008&window_type=print
FREEDOM OF ASSOCIATION. Amy Gutmann, editor. 382pp. Princeton
University Press; distributed in the UK by Wiley. £40 (paperback,
£13.95) - 0 691 05758 3.
Liberal democracies pride themselves on the freedom of association
enjoyed by their citizens. The absence of that freedom is one of the
surest signs of oppression. It is part of being a free person to join
together with others of like mind. When people cannot exercise that
freedom, their liberty is radically diminished. At the same time, the
presence of freedom of association is a marker for a healthy
democracy. Since Tocqueville's writings on American democracy, it has
been a liberal orthodoxy that flourishing associations and strong
democracy go together.
Indisputably, freedom of association is a Good Thing. Like every other
great political good, however, it is attended by numerous
inconveniences, and sometimes it can engender serious evils. Free
association for some may mean disrespect and exclusion for others.
Schools and clubs which limit admission by ethnic origin or sexual
orientation can claim to be exercising their freedom to associate with
others of their choice; but the effect of such choices is to express
contempt for those who do not meet the required criteria and,
arguably, to limit the freedom of association of those thereby shut
out. In an admirably lucid and balanced essay introducing an
exceptionally valuable collection of essays on the subject, Amy
Gutmann discusses the case of Bob Jones University v United States.
The case concerned the US Internal Revenue's withholding of tax-exempt
charitable status from the Bob Jones University on the ground that, in
prohibiting interracial dating among its students, it was practising
racial discrimination. The Bob Jones University could claim that it
was exercising freedom of association, in that the university was a
voluntary religious association based on an interpretation of the
Bible in which miscegenation is forbidden. On the other hand, it could
be argued that any policy that proscribes interracial couples is a
limitation on free association - and a highly discriminatory one at
that. At this point, freedom of association may seem a somewhat
paradoxical good, inasmuch as it can be intelligibly invoked to
justify contradictory policies.
Gutmann comments that the Supreme Court was reasonable and right to
uphold the Internal Revenue's denial of tax-exempt status to the Bob
Jones University. She cites the judgment that a limitation of
religious liberty may be justified if it is essential to accomplish an
overriding governmental interest - in this case, overcoming racial
discrimination in American education. Gutmann is right to endorse the
Supreme Court's decision in this case. Yet neither she nor the
majority of the other contributors to Freedom of Association have
asked themselves whether the theoretical perspective from which they
make such judgments - a theory in which free association is one
element in a system of fundamental human rights - can do justice to
the complex issues surrounding freedom of association in the modern
world. Only four or five of the book's thirteen distinguished
contributors show clear signs of understanding the severe limitations
of a rights-based, juridical approach to the subject.
This curious oversight arises partly from the fact that most
contributors to Freedom of Association treat the subject primarily, if
not solely, as it has arisen in American constitutional history, in
which a discourse of fundamental rights has long been hegemonic. It is
true that a great deal that is useful and enlightening can be said
within this limited context. In a characteristically probing, rigorous
and uncompromising paper on "The Value of Association", George Kateb
argues that freedom of association is indeed a fundamental right that
should not be compromised for the sake of mere gain to society. "The
issue", he writes, "is whether a given activity that is alleged to be
an exercise of a fundamental right injures the vital claims of others,
and hence, is not in fact an exercise of a fundamental right."
Deploying this understanding of rights, Kateb reaches the "painful
conclusion" that governmental interference in the membership policies
of social clubs for the purpose of compelling admission of blacks is
inconsistent with freedom of association.
So long as one remains within the narrow confines of Kateb's argument,
it is hard to fault. But why should anyone feel obliged to accept the
rights-based theory which leads him to his painful conclusion? It is,
in the first place, only a local truth within American jurisprudence
that fundamental rights cannot conflict with one another. Many other
constitutional traditions, such as Canada's, recognize that
fundamental rights can and do clash. When rights clash, a decision
must be reached about which is more important, and one relevant test
of importance is the public interest. Most constitutions resolve
conflicts of rights in this way. Many are ready to impose restrictions
on freedom for the sake of a public interest that the American
Constitution does not allow, including some that have a direct bearing
on freedom of association; nearly all European states have legislation
prohibiting racist speech. Kateb's argument for a fundamental right to
free association proceeds in part by analogy with the near-absolute
protection conferred on free expression in the American Constitution.
But that is an argument which no one who does not already accept
American constitutional conventions on free expression (as recently
interpreted) will find compelling. For many of us, indeed, Kateb's
painful conclusion is a reductio ad absurdum of the peremptory claims
about rights that are its point of departure.
The limitations of the rights-based approach to freedom of association
are recognized by several contributors. In one of the book's subtlest
contributions, "Revisiting the Civic Sphere", Yael Tamir contends
persuasively that a liberal, rights-based account which focuses on its
importance in exemplifying the autonomy of civic associations is in no
way inconsistent with a communitarian argument invoking the forms of
common life that free association makes possible. Will Kymlicka's
essay on "Ethnic Associations and Democratic Citizenship" is a robust
argument that many multicultural policies can be defended as promoting
associational life and thereby the kind of civic engagement that
underpins active democratic citizenship. Alan Ryan's contribution on
"The City as a Site for Free Association" is a useful corrective of
views which ground association in individual engagements and neglect
the role of social institutions such as cities. Stuart White's essay
on "Trade Unionism in a Liberal State" has a broad theoretical
interest in arguing that liberal states are not bound to adhere
strictly to a principle of respecting the organizational autonomy of
trade unions and other secondary associations. Michael Walzer's
contribution on "Involuntary Association" is a thoughtful exploration
of the cultural preconditions of association, voluntary or not.
The essays by Tamir, Kymlicka, Ryan, White and Walzer are exemplary in
directing attention to the social, cultural and political contexts in
which the life of associations arises. In different ways, each can be
read as an argument against the strange notion that debate about
freedom of association can be confined within the Procrustean
framework of rights theory. Perhaps it is beginning to be understood
that a parochial legalist discourse of rights may not be the best
language in which to frame the central questions of political thought.
If this is indeed so, it is not before time.
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list