[Paleopsych] New Criterion: Which Enlightenment? by Keith Windschuttle
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Mon Mar 28 22:32:09 UTC 2005
Enlightenment? by Keith Windschuttle
http://www.newcriterion.com/archive/23/mar05/keith.htm
Gertrude Himmelfarb
The Roads to Modernity:
The British, French, and American Enlightenments.
Knopf, 284 pages, $25
Although it has already attracted a series of reverent reviews
befitting a work by one of today's most eminent practitioners of
history, this book is still more important than it looks. Gertrude
Himmelfarb has called her latest volume Roads to Modernity: The
British, French and American Enlightenments. It can be read as a
provocative and persuasive revision not only of the intellectual era
that made the modern world, but also of the concepts that still
largely determine how we think about human affairs today.
In particular, it explains the source of the fundamental division
that, despite several predictions of its imminent demise, still
doggedly grips Western political life: that between the left and the
right. From the outset, each side had its own philosophical
assumptions and its own view of the human condition. Roads to
Modernity shows why one of these sides has generated a steady progeny
of historical successes while its rival has consistently lurched from
one disaster to the next.
Most historians have accepted for several years now that the
Enlightenment, once popularly characterized as the Age of Reason, came
in two versions, the radical and the skeptical. The former is now
generally identified with France, the latter with Scotland. It has
also been acknowledged that the anti-clericalism that obsessed the
French philosophes was not reciprocated in Britain or America. Indeed,
in both these countries many Enlightenment concepts--human rights,
liberty, equality, tolerance, science, progress--complemented rather
than opposed church thinking.
Himmelfarb has joined this revisionist process and accelerated its
pace dramatically. She argues that, central though many
mid-eighteenth-century Scots were to the movement, there were also so
many original English contributors that a more accurate term than
Scottish would be British Enlightenment.
Moreover, unlike the French who elevated reason to the primary role in
human affairs, British thinkers gave reason a secondary, instrumental
role. In Britain it was virtue that trumped all other qualities. This
was not personal virtue but the "social virtues"--compassion,
benevolence, sympathy--which the British philosophers believed
naturally, instinctively, and habitually bound people to one another.
In the abstract, this difference might seem merely one of degree but,
as it worked itself out in the subsequent history of the Continent and
the British Isles, it was profound.
In making her case, Himmelfarb defines the British Enlightenment in
terms that some might find surprising. She includes people who in the
past have usually been labeled part of the Counter-Enlightenment,
especially John Wesley and Edmund Burke. She assigns prominent roles
to the social movements of Methodism and Evangelical philanthropy.
Despite the fact that the American colonies rebelled from Britain to
found a republic, Himmelfarb demonstrates how very close they were to
the British Enlightenment and how distant from French republicans.
These differences have remained to this day, and over much the same
issues. On the one hand, in France, the ideology of reason challenged
not only religion and the church but all the institutions dependent
upon them. Reason was inherently subversive. On the other hand,
British moral philosophy was reformist rather than radical, respectful
of both the past and present, even while looking forward to a more
enlightened future. It was optimistic and had no quarrel with
religion, which was why, in both Britain and the United States, the
church itself could become a principal source for the spread of
enlightened ideas.
In Britain, the elevation of the social virtues derived from both
academic philosophy and religious practice. In the eighteenth century,
the professor of moral philosophy at Glasgow University, Adam Smith,
was more celebrated for his Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759) than his
later thesis on the wealth of nations. He argued that sympathy and
benevolence were moral virtues that sprang directly from the human
condition. In being virtuous, especially towards those who could not
help themselves, man rewarded himself by fulfilling his human nature.
Edmund Burke began public life as a disciple of Smith. He wrote an
early pamphlet on scarcity which endorsed Smith's laissez faire
approach as the best way to serve both economic activity in general
and the lower orders in particular. His Counter- Enlightenment status
is usually assigned for his critique of the French Revolution, but
Burke was at the same time a supporter of American independence. While
his own government was pursuing its military campaign in America (and,
at the same time, suspending habeas corpus at home), Burke was urging
it to respect the liberty of both Americans and Englishmen.
While some historians have been led by this apparent paradox to claim
that at different stages of his life there were two Edmund Burkes, one
liberal and the other conservative, Himmelfarb disagrees. She argues
that his views were always consistent with the ideas about moral
virtue that permeated the whole of the British Enlightenment. Indeed,
Burke took this philosophy a step further by making the "sentiments,
manners and moral opinion" of men the basis not only of social
relations but also of politics.
Apart from the different philosophical status they assigned to reason
and virtue, the one issue where the division between the British and
Continental Enlightenments was most sharply contrasted was their
attitude to the lower orders. This is a distinction that has
reverberated through politics ever since. The radical heirs of the
Jacobin tradition have always insisted that it is they who speak for
the wretched of the earth. In eighteenth-century France they claimed
to speak for the people and the general will. In the nineteenth
century they said they represented the working classes against their
capitalist exploiters. In our own time, they have claimed to be on the
side of blacks, women, gays, indigenes, refugees, and anyone else they
define as the victims of discrimination and oppression. Himmelfarb's
study demonstrates what a façade these claims actually are.
The French philosophes thought the social classes were divided by the
chasm of poverty and, more crucially, of superstition and ignorance.
They despised the lower orders because they were in thrall to
Christianity. The editor of the Encyclopédie, Denis Diderot, declared
the common people had no role in the Age of Reason. "The general mass
of men are not so made that they can either promote or understand this
forward march of the human spirit." Indeed, "the common people are
incredibly stupid," he said, and were little more than beasts: "too
idiotic--bestial--too miserable, and too busy" to enlighten
themselves. Voltaire agreed. The lower orders lacked the intellect
required to reason and so must be left to wallow in superstition. They
could be controlled and pacified only by the sanctions and strictures
of religion which, Voltaire proclaimed, "must be destroyed among
respectable people and left to the canaille large and small, for whom
it was made."
In Britain and America, by contrast, the chasm between rich and poor
was bridged by the moral sense and common sense the Enlightenment
attributed to all individuals. Everyone, including the members of the
lower orders, had a common humanity and a common fund of moral and
social obligations. It was this social ethos, Himmelfarb argues, that
in the English-speaking world was the common denominator between Adam
Smith, Edmund Burke, secular philosophers, religious enthusiasts,
Church of England bishops, and Wesleyan preachers.
"Man is by constitution a religious animal," Edmund Burke famously
wrote in his Reflections on the Revolution in France. For Burke,
religion itself--religious dissent in particular--was the very basis
of liberty. The Wesleyans went one step further and also made it the
basis of social reform.
John Wesley's great mission was intended to be not only the spiritual
salvation of the poor but also their intellectual and moral
edification. There was no conflict between reason and religion. "It is
a fundamental principle with us," Wesley argued, "that to renounce
reason is to renounce religion, that religion and reason go hand in
hand, and that all irrational religion is false religion." It was only
by "religion and reason joined" that "passion and prejudice" and
"wickedness and bigotry" could be overcome.
In pursuit of their mission, the Methodists produced a huge volume of
literature not just on Christianity but on grammar, medicine,
electricity, natural history, Shakespeare, Milton, Spenser, Locke, and
other classics. Himmelfarb observes: "The whole of this quite
extraordinary publication industry, comprising books, pamphlets, and
tracts on a variety of subjects and directed to different levels of
literacy and interest, constituted something like an Enlightenment for
the common man."
Methodists also took the initiative in the distribution of food,
clothing, and money to the needy, paid visits to the sick and to
prisoners in jail, and set up loan funds and work projects for the
unemployed. By the end of the eighteenth century, the example of
Wesleyanism had spawned an Evangelical movement within the Church of
England that appealed largely to the middle and upper classes. As well
as movements for prison reform, education and poor relief, the
Evangelicals led the campaign that eventually lobbied successfully for
the abolition of the slave trade.
In the American colonies, the first Great Awakening, the religious
revival of the 1730s and early 1740s, paralleled the Methodist revival
in Britain. The contrast with France was dramatic. In seeking respite
from the religious passions of the Old World, Himmelfarb writes, the
Americans did not, like the French, turn against religion itself.
Instead, they incorporated religion into the mores of society. They
"moralized" and "socialized" religion, turning its energies into
movements for voluntary association, local organization and,
ultimately, the politics of liberty.
In Britain and America, those who wrote about social reform and those
in government who could do something about it were either the same
people or else people cooperating closely with one another. In France,
however, the philosophes were unconstrained by practical
considerations about how their ideas might be translated into reality.
They were all the more free to theorize and generalize precisely
because they were less free to consult and advise.
This profoundly affected the political consequences of their ideas.
The philosophes initially decided that enlightened despotism would be
their political instrument of choice. "Enlightened despotism,"
Himmelfarb argues, "was an attempt to realize--to enthrone as it
were--reason as embodied in the person of an enlightened monarch, a
Frederick enlightened by Voltaire, a Catherine by Diderot." The
failure of these attempts subsequently produced the theory of the
"general will" that legitimized the terror of the French Revolution.
The people, in whose name the revolution purportedly acted, was a
singular abstraction, represented by an appropriately singular and
abstract general will. "In effect, the theory of the general will was
a surrogate for the enlightened despot. It had the same moral and
political authority as the despot because it, too, was grounded in
reason, a reason that was the source of all legitimate authority."
Within England itself, there were supporters of the French
Enlightenment whose theory and practice ended up little different to
that of the philosophes they emulated. Himmelfarb has a chapter on
British radical dissenters, much of which is devoted to the pathetic
case of William Godwin, whose writings denigrated emotions and
sexuality as irrational but whose personal life was a tangle of both.
As in France, the English radicals devised theories about the
education of children, but their only contribution to education reform
involved the schooling of the middle and upper classes. Godwin's wife,
Mary Wollstonecraft, wanted girls to be educated with boys, but her
thoughts were confined to those who could afford to go to boarding
schools.
Meanwhile, education for the poor became an important cause for
Methodism and Evangelicalism. The eighteenth-century essayists and
politicians Joseph Addison and Richard Steele thought the founding of
charity schools for the children of the poor were "the glory of the
age," the "greatest instance of public spirit the age has produced."
They were followed by Sunday Schools which, until the mass education
movements of the nineteenth century, were the main source of
instruction for the lower orders in reading, writing and arithmetic.
These education reforms reflected the same sensibility and ethos that
inspired the other British philanthropic movements. They derived from
the Christian principle, reaffirmed by British moral philosophy, of
the natural equality of all people. In his treatise on the wealth of
nations, the subject of Adam Smith's title was not the modern nation
state. He meant the people who composed the nation, especially the
"lower ranks." It was their well-being, their "wealth" that would be
promoted by a progressive political economy. Smith wrote:
No society can surely be flourishing and happy, of which the
greater part of the members are poor and miserable. It is but
equity, besides, that they who feed, clothe, and lodge the whole
body of the people should have such a share of the produce of their
own labor as to be themselves tolerably well fed, clothed, and
lodged.
In Britain and America, the Enlightenment was both a theoretical and a
practical expression of this outlook. Religion, moral philosophy, and
their egalitarian assumptions shaped the era. They worked together for
the common cause: the material as well as the "moral reformation" of
the people. Roads to Modernity reveals more clearly than any previous
book on the subject the environment in which these ideas and practices
were born and how firmly they still mold the moral sense and common
sense of the English-speaking world today.
_________________________________________________________________
Keith Windschuttle's latest book is The Fabrication of Aboriginal
History, Volume One, Van Diemen's Land 1803-1847 (Macleay Press).
________________________________________________________
From The New Criterion Vol. 23, No. 7, March 2005
References
1. http://www.newcriterion.com/archive/23/mar05/keith.htm
2. http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/ASIN/1400042364/thenewcriterio
3. http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/ASIN/1400042364/thenewcriterio
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list