[Paleopsych] R.A. Sharpe: Philosophical Pluralism
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Wed May 18 22:53:30 UTC 2005
Philosophical Pluralism*
Review Discussion
R.A. Sharpe University of Wales, Lampeter
Inquiry 42: 129-41 (prob. 1989)
* Avrum Stroll, Sketches of Landscapes: PhilosophybyExample (Cambridge,
MA/London: Bradford Books, MIT Press, 1998), xiv + 282 pp., ISBN 0262193914,
£29.50.
Avrum Stroll s new book is pluralist. He repudiates overarchingtheory or the
single conceptual model in favour of the description of what he sees as a
varied, ununi® ed landscape of concepts, and in his perambulations through
this countryside he touches on topics as varied as scepticism, reference in
fiction and reference to natural kinds, Platonism and more, discussions unified
more by a common outlook than by any single theme. The common perspective is
that he repudiates the `masterkey approach. He is struck by the diversity of
philosophical problems and the diversity of the answers to them and in this his
approach is somewhat Wittgensteinian. He calls it `piecemeal .
The opening discussion is a fairly lengthy examination of scepticism. Professor
Stroll applies the diallelus or `wheel argument widely. The gist of the
diallelus is this. Ifwe are to know how things really are as opposedto how they
appear to us, we need a criterion to distinguishthe apparent from the real. But
of any criterion which may be offered we can ask `Does this criterion succeed
in distinguishing the apparent from the real? To know that it succeeds is
already to be able to distinguish and this assumes we are in prior possession
of a criterion for distinguishing seeming from reality. The search for criteria
looks to be viciously circular. Stroll extends this argument to beliefs as well
as to appearances; then the same objection applies; any criterion for
distinguishing true beliefs from false assumes that we already have a means of
detecting which beliefs are true and which not, so we need to be already in
possession of the criterion we seek.
Stroll links the discussion of criteria for beliefs with the use of criteria in
grading. The suggestion that we might be able to grade beliefs as we grade,
say, fruit goes back at least as far as Descartes s introduction, in his
objections and replies on Meditation One, of the apple barrel metaphor.
Remember that the idea was that we should sort through beliefs casting out
those which did not come up to scratch. Stroll does not challenge the analogy.
However, there are reasons for supposing the apple barrel an illjudged
metaphor.
First, what sense does it make to speak of beliefs as good or bad? Stroll seems
to think there are no problems, but it is clear that we do not ordinarily speak
this way. The very idea of sorting through beliefs, dividing them into good and
bad beliefs, is bizarre. For to identify a belief as a bad belief (assuming
this is an epistemological matter) is already to make it impossible to believe
it. If I see that it lacks evidential support etc. then I willnot believe it.
(ceteris paribus). (Ifthe badness of a belief is a moralmatter rather than an
epistemological one, then, I suppose, we may think a belief to have morally
objectionable implications but still believe it because we think it true; a
racist might think another race both intellectually and morally inferior,
recognize that this view has regrettable consequences as far as their treatment
is concerned but, with a sigh, register it as a sad but unavoidable fact. In
such a case the proposition might be both taken to be bad and believable.) The
second reason why this model is unhelpful is that the holism of beliefs makes
it impossible to weed out beliefs one at a time. Of course, in one respect, the
apple barrel metaphor is not so inapposite; it suggests that one bad belief
infects the others; and it is true that if I have one wrong belief I will have
others and that the removal of this false belief has knockon effects. (Though
in as much as the metaphor suggests this is a temporal process it is
misleading.) If I come to believe that the computer model for the mind is
mistaken, then all sorts of things follow. I do not just relinquish this
belief, I will also cease to believe in the claims of `cognitive science about
many other matters. Still the analogy fails in as much as I do not scrutinize
these connected beliefs separately.(It is doubtfulas to whether Descartes
thought ofthe matter in this way;wrongly, he thoughtof beliefs as items which
can be separately scrutinized, which suggests he had some other view of the
infecting process.)
So, given that the criterion for relinquishing a belief is that you now either
have reason to believe that it is false or you see that there is no reason to
believe it true, the analogywithapples does not run through. For the content of
the belief is intimately connected with the change. In the first, stronger
case, you see that the propositional content of the belief is false. So the
grounds for rejecting it are necessarily connected with your belief. Once you
see that it is false, necessarily you cannot believe it (barring irrationality
and doublethink etc.)It ceases to be a proposition you believe.It is, then, no
longer one of your beliefs. What you believe changes from it to its contrary or
contradictory.
As we see, in the centralsense of `belief , beliefs are no longer in existence
if they are not believed. But the criteria for goodness in an apple, firmness,
texture, andtaste, are independent ofthe fact that it is an apple. If it fails
these criteria it does not cease to be an apple; it is merely a bad apple and
it might, unfortunately, be your apple. The dissimilarities go further, of
course. I have spoken of `mybeliefs±with the implication that this ceases to
be one of my beliefs once I see it to be false or groundless. But others might
continue to believe this proposition ± even where I try to dissuade them. The
purchase of an apple precludes its purchase by somebody else.
Why should the analogy with apples have seemed a good parallel to anybody?
Perhaps the fact that `beliefis sometimes taken to be equivalent to
`proposition lends Descartes s argument an unmerited degree of plausibility.
For propositions continue to exist when they are not being entertained and, if
beliefs are taken in that sense the objection that, normally, negative grading
produces extinction, will not apply.
To return to the diallelus, the assumption is that criteria needto be
justified. But there seems no more reason to believe this than to assume that
justifications in general have themselves to be always justified ± a move which
is evidently regressive. As Wittgenstein famously observed, `justifications
have to stop somewhere(the precise reverse of an equally famous dictum of
Charles Sanders Peirce). There is reason for supposing Wittgenstein right;
criteria do not generally invite the regressive move; primarily there is the
observation that if the criterion of a good apple is that it is crispand has a
strongslightlyacidic ¯ avour, we seem under no pressure to answer the question,
`But how do you know that this criterion is a rightone or
1
a good one? It just is the one commonly used ± or at the very least, the one
used by the speaker. If pushed, I would invite people to taste certain apples,
but then, if they did not agree I might conclude that they had defective taste
buds or whatever. The moves are familiar in aesthetics. In as much as the
judgment of an apple ultimately depends upon preference, there is no case for
supposing it potentially regressive in the way that epistemic notions are,
rightly or wrongly, imagined to be.
A point to notice is that there are people who are more or less competent in
grading. A sommelier might reject a wine for reasons not obvious to me. But it
would be odd, and perhaps implausible for me to question the criteria used.
Doubts about his judgment would not usually present themselves as invitations
to him to `justify his criteria .For what more could be required than the
recognition that he is qualified in this area. David Hume memorably summarized
the requirements for a good judge in his `Of the standard of taste ; `strong
sense, united to delicate sentiment, improved by practice, perfected by
comparison and cleared of all prejudice. This does not, of course, preclude
the assessor making a bad judgment say in making a judgment which is rejected
by all his peers, and a number of misjudgments will lead us to conclude that he
is not an expert.
Let s return to the analogy between apples and beliefs. There are experts in
grading apples. Are there also experts in settling beliefs? Part of the history
of epistemologyhas been premised on the assumption that people could improve
their capacities in this in a general sort of way, mainlyby a trainingin logic.
I am somewhat sceptical. The fact is that the imprudent acquiescence in a
belief is usually a result of unfamiliarity with the area and not a general
failing. It is not usually an inability to employ modus ponens that is the
problem. A man who has a symptom which he knows to be one of the symptoms of
something serious like cancer may jump to the conclusion that he has that
disease, where an expert, aware of the fact that any one symptom can indicate
any one of a number of conditions or nothing very serious at all, will be far
more cautious. If my car fails to start I may leap to the conclusion that it
must be the coil because it was that which caused it to fail to start
previously;but a mechanic, aware of the various factors which prevent a car
from starting, mightcarryout further tests. Itwould be consistent with Stroll
s general position to acknowledge this. The dissimilarity between grading
apples and grading beliefs is this. There are experts in grading apples but
there are no experts in grading beliefs. There are experts in grading beliefs
according to their implausibility or plausibility in various areas. There are
experts on oncology, car mechanics, the history of music, performance practice,
the history of philosophy etc., but there are no experts on beliefs per se and
the idea that philosophy might produce these is absurd. For to be good in any
of these areas is to be aware of the range of pros and cons. If a philosophy
teacher marks an essay on his special field, he can do so because he is aware
of the arguments which are available against even the most plausible seeming
position, the thesis which seems innocuous to the student. But in this respect
he does not differ from the historian of the industrial revolution who also
knows that what looks obvious has been questioned. Those of us who teach a
subject like aesthetics know how ready teachers of Englishare to propounda
theory unaware that the theoryitself has a history of defence and refutation.
Stroll is not, I think, either Wittgensteinian enough or pluralist enough both
here, and as I shall argue, elsewhere.
Neither does Stroll seem to have considered that a justification is essentially
contextbound. We ask for justifications in situations where the claims made
seem controvertible. This connects with a more basic and perhaps more
significant mistake. The error is to think of `criteria for belief as though
this is a matter to be settled at a general level. It is not even clear that
such a notion makes any sense. Ofcourse, one might present the anodyne,
`Believe what you have good evidence for , as a maxim but this manages to be
both boring and dangerous. Not only does it not register the way beliefs
connect with loyalties and commitments but observing it, were it possible,
would be destructive. Do I trust my friends only as far as the evidence
supports that trust? In such cases the interconnection between my belief that
my friend is reliable and my moral commitment to him makes the matter of my
assessment of any evidence that he is untrustworthy a much more complex matter
than merely looking at evidence. Evidence that I would take at face value if he
were somebody else, I may not accept because he is my friend. Imaylook for
other and more generous explanations of his behaviour.
Stroll is well aware of cases where no justification for a belief claim is
required. His examples of what we might know but cannot justify are cases like
somebody with perfect pitch identifying a note, or an idiot savant coming up
withthe square root of 1,973. Consider some other cases. I know what my name
is, straight off; admittedly, there might be contexts in which I might be
called upon to produce evidence; I might be called on to produce evidence if
fraud is a possibility, as when Iam gettinga new passport or openinga bank
account. A hospital doctor might ask me for evidence that I am whom I am if I
am being admittedto casualty because of a bang on the head. Evidence would not
be normally called for when introducing myself at a party. The requirement to
produce evidence there suggests that your host is a maniac or a joker, or a
philosophy undergraduate, or that this is a party where unwelcome gatecrashers
are expected. The point is, surely, that context rules, and I am not sure that
Stroll makes enough of it. I might be required to produce evidence that the
earth has existed for millions of years in the Bible Belt whereas this is not a
challenge I would normally expect.
This connects with the discussion of Wittgenstein and Moore on certainty.
Strollconsiders G. E. Moore s attack on scepticism.Unexpectedly, he takes
Moore to be asserting what he calls a `private statement in claiming that he
knows that the world existed long before he was born. The claim is initially
puzzling. Does Stroll have in mind a case like a sensedatum judgment where
privileged access means that I, and only I, am the authority for the claim;
this looks the obvious model for a `private statement should one exist. But
this is quite unlike the examples offered by Moore. Stroll goes on to say that
rather than a justification being `silent , there seems no place for one at
all in this case. (This he takes to be the gist of Wittgenstein s remarks at
On Certainty 84). A silent or private justification is impossible because of
the publicityof the notion of justification (p. 21); on the basis of this he
goes on to argue that there cannot be relevant evidence for the judgment if it
is private. Stroll certainly misunderstands Wittgenstein here because
Wittgenstein would not have levelled that objection at Moore, as Stroll seems
to think. The context I think makes it clear that, when Wittgenstein says that
it is of no interest what particular things Moore knows but how these are
known, it is not the question of justification to which Wittgenstein alludes to
so much as the fact, as he goes on to stress, that these are things we all know
but cannot say how. The issue is a general one. In one of those rhetorical
questions which needs to be taken as an assertion, Wittgenstein goes on to
saythat this is a truism which is never called into question (OC 87); it is
part of our `frame of reference (OC 83). The presentation suggests that Stroll
thinks that this has something to do withthe privatelanguage argument (p.
21)but, if he does, he is wrong. Note, as well, that this example is different
from the sorts of example which Stroll himself uses, that I see straight off
that one shade is darker than another. Stroll is correct in what he says about
this but it is not the sort of example Wittgenstein discusses in this passage.
Wittgenstein is concerned with judgments which form a sort of bed rock, such as
the earth is round or that it has existed for a verylongtime, but these beliefs
mightnot be shared by other cultures.
The second part of the discussion of scepticism attempts to unpin the Cartesian
dream argument. Stroll begins withthe observation that Descartes s
presentation assumes that he knows, on occasion, that he is not asleep (p. 28);
Stroll thinks this undermines the argument. For the argument proceeds from the
premise that sometimes I have been asleep and dreamt that I was awake to the
conclusion that, at any time, I might be dreaming, unbeknown to myself.
2
Stroll s is what Curley called the `procedural argument ± that if the
conclusion is true Descartes could not assert its premise, and it is a very
familiar objection to the Cartesian argument from dreaming. But, as Curley
argues, it surely is enough cause for concern that the conclusion of the dream
argument proceeds validly from premises we believed on re¯ ection to be true.
Descartes is concerned with the possibility that he thinks that he is awake but
is in fact asleep (something he later discovers). At any point he may think he
is awake but not be. The scepticalthrust is unblunted and it preserves its
point in the face of Stroll s argument that `dwellingcarefully , whichwe are
called on to do, is not something which can intelligiblybe done whilst asleep
(p. 30). Certainly if I do this, as opposed to dreaming that I do it, I am not
asleep, but the possibility that I dream that I dwell carefully is not ruled
out. This is a close relative of the familiar point that I cannot assert whilst
I am asleep, which does not, of course, rule out the possibility that I dream
that I assert. So Bernard Williams s objection that Descartes seems to think
that in dreaming
3
we make rational judgments but on the wrong basis identifies a mistake in
Descartes s presentation but not one which has any purchase on the sceptical
force of it. If I dream that Imake rational judgments rather than make rational
judgments on the basis of what I dream, the sceptical argument can still carry
through.
The problem with Stroll s presentation is that he seems not to grasp the
sceptical method Descartes uses; it is, like so many forms of scepticism, a
matter of beginning with the assumption that we know and then, showing, by
argument, that our confidence is misplaced. It is an assemblage of familiar
considerations which leads to scepticism. The argument is a reductio. I know
that I am awake but, since I have sometimes been mistaken about this, I have to
allow the possibility that I am now asleep and that the judgments I now make
are not judgments or assertions at all. Rather that I dream that I judge that
Iam awake. What mistake Descartes makes is concealed in the thesis that there
are no certain signs that I am awake rather than dreaming. For the situation is
not symmetrical. Awake, I know I am not dreaming and there are tests I can
apply, such as pinching myself. Kenny said that in a lecture J. L. Austin
claimed there were fifty such indications. One of these is described by
Descartes himself, the continuity of waking life as opposed to the
discontinuity of dreaming. There are, then, tests which establish that I am
awake, providing one does not demand, as Descartes presumably would,
unreasonably high standards for `certain . There are no tests which I can
apply which establish that I am asleep for, in sleep, I can make no judgments.
There follows a pair of essays critical of Putnam and Kripke s wellknown
account of the meaning of naturalkind terms. Stroll s counters are so
ingenuous that it is hard to understand why they have not been considered
before. (Perhaps they have, but Stroll does not cite any previous sources and
the criticisms are certainly new to me.) The thesis that water is identical
with H2O and that `water both means H2O and meant H2O before that fact was
discovered is open to the following objections.
1. Firstofall, water is not identicalwith H2O. There are various isotopes of
water. Pure water is a mixture of molecules other than H2O such as D2O, HDO and
T2O which have different boiling points and masses. One of them, `heavy
wateris familiar by name to the general public.
2.By thetransitivity of identity,if water =H2O and H2O =icethen water = ice,
which is false. He concludes that neither identity is true.
(These mistakes are notconfinedto Putnam and Kripke;theyare also found in
J. J. C. Smart.)
3. There are substances known as isomers whose constituents are the same but
since the arrangements of atoms and molecules are different, the substances
differ. Ethyl alcohol (C2H5OH) and methyl ether (CH3OCH3) are each composed of
two carbon, six hydrogen and one oxygen atom but the structure in each case
differs.
Well, we can all have horse laughs at the expense of Putnam and Kripke who, for
all their kowtowing to the natural sciences, were apparently ignorant of some
very elementary highschool chemistry and apparently did not bother to check.
(In my case, I feel embarrassed at repeating these errors to generations of
students, and puzzled why none of them told me.) But what does all this show?
Putnam and Kripke will simply replace their initial statement of identity with
a more complex form which might be disjunctive.
Still, a few knockabout arguments are fun and the discomforture of the mightyis
always agreeable. The positive thesis of Stroll, that the phenomenal character
of water is the basis for its meaning and takes precedence over the
microphysical is independent of these particular swipes. Children, he says,
could not otherwise learn the meaning of `water since they cannot perceive the
microstructure (pp. 56±57, 60). At this point Stroll, exhilarated by the chase,
will pick up anything to hurl at the retreating figures of Putnam and Kripke.
No!, the child cannot see the microstructure. But it is no skin off Putnam and
Kripke s noses to allow that children learn the use of water through its
phenomenal properties and then be corrected if the sample of water failed to
have the usual microstructural properties. This happens with a distinction like
that between gold and fool s gold. I cannot tell the difference any more than
I can between 18 and 9 carat gold, or between grades of diamond. Ofcourse, even
ifwe need instruments to check, the distinction is ultimately phenomenal in
that we can, eventually, learn how to use the right instruments to check and
see for ourselves; for all I know, there may be simple tests to be done on the
spot which show the difference between gold and iron pyrites. This is only an
extension of something familiar. I am not very good at picking out different
sorts of trees or birds where other people are very good at it. There is a role
for the expert or the knowledgeable here. I know this is a bird but don t know
that it is a willow warbler though I do know that a willow warbler is a bird.
(My books on ornithology make it clear that it is very hard to tell members of
the warbler family apart. For example, the Marsh Warbler is described as `very
like the Reed Warbler in appearance but less common .)
Stroll neglects the intuitively correct and important notion ofthe linguistic
division of labour. The important question is surely whether or not we speak of
the meaning of water having changed as more precise criteria become available.
Itcertainly strikes me as implausible to suppose that medieval man, unbeknown
to himself, operated with a concept of water that was microstructural before
chemical analysis was practised or even thought about. Linguistic competence
cannot be like that, surely. The point ought to be that knowingwhat water means
is not easily distinguished from knowing the facts about water, and some of
these facts may be more or less arcane. The factlanguage gap is surely a
philosophical miscalculation and we owe to Quine the realization that the
matter of what a word means shades imperceptibly into general facts about those
things to which it applies.
In the next chapter, Stroll introduces a functional element in the definition
ofsome natural kindwords such as `jade or `water ;this plays at least some
role in the definition though it is less prominent than in the case of words
for artefacts like `table or `knife . Such natural kind words have been
labelled `rigid designators . Ifwater is a rigid designator, Strollreasons,
then it follows that if `watervanished from the face ofthe earth, we would
lose the meaning of `water . We would not, hence `water is not a rigid
designator. But the theory of rigid designation does not carry this
consequence. It applies also to proper names where it at least succeeds in
accountingfor the fact that we refer to Homer without even knowing whether the
one thing traditionally attributed to him, the authorship of the Iliad, is
true. And Homer is no longer with us. In the event of water disappearing,
`water would act more like a proper name.
Naturally enough, the discussion progresses to the matter of fictional
statements via some consideration of Kripke s notion of rigid designators ± or
`tagging , as we should perhaps call it in deference to Ruth Barcan Marcus.
What do we do about the names offictionalcharacters andobjects? Go for a
fictional operator allowing that fictive objects `exist in fiction and
therefore can be tagged, presumably, in another possible world? Abandon the
idea that proper names are rigid designators because here nothing designated
exists? Abandon the reference theory for fictional objects in favour of the
Russellian account for fictional names, that in fiction a proper name may equal
a description? Hold that fictional names are secondary or derivative?
Stroll is convincedthat the intuitive view is that these are proper names and
that this commonsense view is right. He argues for this via a discussion of
Strawson s `On Referring , whose contribution to the topic he believes is
undulyneglected. Strawson denies thatfictionalsentences are either false or
nonsensical. Rather these sentences are used to make statements that are
neither true nor false (their truth or falsity `does not arise ). Strawson is
obviously wrong here and Stroll obviously right.Thus it is true to say that
Lady Dedlock was the mother of Esther Summerson and false to saythat Mrs
Jellyby was childless. The principle that you cannot refer to what is
nonexistent is either trivial or false. On the ordinary understanding of
`refer we regularly refer to fictional objects. To make the trivial point that
fictional people and places do not exist by means of the observation `Fictional
names do not refermerely adjusts the sense of `referin a tendentious way.That
wonderfulfilm byTruffaut, Fahrenheit 451, crystalizes the role played on our
lives byfiction. To say that we cannot so refer trivializes the question byan
arbitrary redefinition of `refer . So far Stroll seems to me to have hit the
bull seye; but his general remarks on fictional statements are less well
judged. The strength of Strawson s analysis, he thinks, is the suggestion that
works of fiction deal with `makebelieve (p. 74) and that, in making this
move, Strawson had shifted the centre of interest from the question of ontology
to the question of the nature offictional discourse.(He does not mention
Kendall Walton in this connection, the philosopher most closely associated with
the idea of `makebelieve ).
What work does `makebelieve do here? My absorption in the narrative of a
story is not preceded by any act of makingbelieve on my part. There is no such
intention and `makebelieve , unlike being deceived, is something
consciouslydone. Ifindthat, once I `get into a story, Isimplyfollow it. When I
saythat Icannot do this, what I mean is that the storydoes not grip, it seems
artificial and preposterous, but this is pretty rare. I follow even a bad film.
So `makebelieve , as an account of how we followfictionalnarratives and as a
basis for fictional reference, is either trivial or false for precisely the
same reasons as the original thesis that we cannot refer to fictional objects.
On the ordinary understanding of `makebelieve this is not what we do when we
watch a film or a play. On a revised definition, we have something made
trivially true through the definition.
In an original discussion of natural languages (English, of course), Stroll
touches on a topic which has broader resonances still, for it links with the
programme of analysis which has dominated philosophy for so much of this
century. In Plato s handling of participation and mimesis, the two concepts
which articulate different versions of the theory of Forms, Plato assumes that
universals are not identical with particulars because they are of a higher type
(pp. 66±67). In a lengthy and somewhat Austinian taxonomic discussion, Stroll
distinguishes three major groupings in natural languages, `clusters , `chains
, and `rings . Imagine a word association procedure motivated by linguistic
interests in synonymy and partial synonymy rather than by psychoanalytic
theories and you will get the picture. In some cases you will be led back to
the word with which you began or a synonym of it. This is what he calls a
`chain . In some cases the two terms, though differing in sound, are
interdefinable.These constitute a `ring .Chainshave rules which determine
membership. The clarification of these ideas considers concepts like `example
, `instance , `model , `copy , `reproduction etc. and leads Stroll to
conclude that Plato con¯ ates a number of different usages (p. 141). To give
just one or two of his examples, a copy is a copy of some particular thing and
a copy is made by man; it follows that the only particulars which could be
copies of forms would be artefacts and, furthermore, that the Forms themselves,
if copied, must be particulars. Now there some objections to this general
thesis which Stroll does not consider. The upshot is that usage is even more
variegated than Stroll s particularism seems to comprehend. For the thesis
carries the implication that if I copy Beethoven s `Les Adieux sonata then I
copy this printed or manuscript token but not the sonata itself, which seems to
me counterintuitive; at the very least, I find myself under no pressure to say
the one rather than the other. I am equally comfortable saying I copied the
sonata or copied this particular token. Again, Stroll suggests that it cannot
follow that a copy must be of a `different orderfrom the original.Quite the
reverse, he thinks; a duplicate key is also a key. But here again, the arts
provide counterexamples; amongst aestheticians Stuart Hampshire s point is
often recapitulated; in general, a copy of a work of art is not itself a work
of art. Copy a work of art and you do not have something which is, in the
important respect, of the same order as the original. Secondly Stroll argues
that samples and examples differ, not in ontology but in the uses to which they
are put. (Stroll says `logic but `ontology better captures the thought.) Thus
a piece ofcloth can be an example ofcloth (if the person to whom it is being
shown does not know what cloth is) or a sample (if he wants to see a swatch of
this particular weave). Stroll draws the powerfully antiPlatonist conclusion
that if you do not know what x is, an example will show you; you will not be
helped by being referred to a universal which cannot be inspected.
This might look like a mere restatement of empiricism but empiricism is placed
in a new light by this approach. However we might be troubled by two thoughts.
First, why should we think Plato would be concerned with departures from the
logic of ordinary talk? Certainly he ought to be fazed by the last point, but I
am not sure he would be. His reaction would almost certainly be `so much the
worse for ordinary distinctions ; secondly, he would presumably argue that
something like intellectual intuition accounts for mathematical knowledge.
Other forms of knowledge are inferior and ought not to be privileged in
philosophical enterprises. He could certainly have adopted a revisionist
approach and would have done so had the objection been put to him. Finally, to
assume that such conceptual entanglements carry through from English into Greek
is probably already to concede some sort of realism, because it can only be on
the basis that facts dictate our conceptual ordering that this is likely to be
so. Otherwise, if they do correspond, it is a mere accident that they
correspond.
Lastly, why should we trust these classifications into chains, rings etc.? They
are based, as Stroll says, on the use of a decent dictionary like Websters. But
what authority has Websters that it should be used in this way? The
classification of words is, after all, not like the classification of natural
kinds. That, too, can go drastically wrongbut there are principled ways of
correcting it through our grasp of natural kinds and our understanding of the
causal order which puts whales in a differentclade fromfish. (Which is not to
disregardthe fact that the taxonomy of living species is the occasion of more
illtempered controversies than most ± puzzling when you consider that these
disagreements seem in principle settleable.) But there are no parallel
principled ways in which we can be reasonably confident that a cluster or a
ring contains all the relevant words.
As I remarked at the beginning, Stroll favours a piecemeal approach to
concepts. That a particularist descriptive approach to philosophy is the
correct one suggests that our concepts may not, generally, be systematic. By
this I mean that there will, for most of our concepts, be no clear boundaries
within which they apply and beyond which they do not. This is particularly so
with concepts like knowledge, belief, justification, human identity, art, right
action, ± indeed pretty well all the concepts in which philosophers are
especially interested. Borderline cases usually require a decision and, though
there may be grounds for that decision, those grounds may also con¯ ict and the
decision may be arbitrary.
Stroll has no theory to account for his piecemeal, Wittgensteinish,
examplebased approach. Should he? Well, of course, in one way even a higher
level picture of why we have our concepts of reference, knowledge, universals
etc. runs counter to his avowedly descriptivist approach and he may shy away
from any justification of it.
But I think something can be said ± though not by an echtWittgensteinian. The
dedicated followers of Wittgenstein eschew any attempt at generalization at all
and in making some tentative suggestions I adulterate the pure milk of the
doctrine. I am going to suggest that a justification for Stroll s approach can
be found in the theory of action. Austin pointed the way towards making the
theory of action primitive in philosophical explanation by making it basic to
what this century has regarded as the fundamental philosophical discipline, the
philosophy of language. (There is an interesting book to be written on the way
that different branches of philosophy have been, in turn, privileged;
philosophy of religion, epistemology, philosophy of language, philosophy of
mind, perhaps aesthetics for a short period in German romanticism.) For Austin,
through the idea of speechacts, elaborated the Wittgensteinian idea that `in
the beginning is the deed . Such a picture does not, of itself, imply that our
concepts outrun our capacity to determine them in a formal way, but it is easy
to see why such a theory should suggest itself. A fundamental distinction in
philosophy of action is between what we consciously intend and what we do,
either foreseeing it and not intending, or do as the unforeseen consequence of
our actions. The words we use determine the concepts we possess in a
straightforward way. Our concept of a planet consists in a number of features
of planets which trivially follow from the use of the word together with some
general truths which might or might not be part of the meaning. (There is no
way of clearly distinguishing questions of fact and language where the matters
of fact are pretty well universally known.) What is the domain of a concept
like the concept of a planet? In this case it seems likely to be determinate.
But there are many concepts whose domain is notoriously indeterminate, such as
that of a tort or, paradigmatically, a work of art. If a previously
unencountered artefact is declared a work of art, of course it might be
unequivocally, and with universal consent, declared thus even though nobody has
considered the case before. The case is unforeseen but it happens that the
lines of the concept have been drawn by implication from previous usages. But
then again there will be cases where previous usage is no guide to what we
should say about this case. Then we make a decision (or some one individual
decides); there may be a preponderance of reasons in favour of counting this an
instance of the concept in question or there may not. The degree of fiat in the
decision will vary. My point is that there is no reason to suppose our concepts
to be more articulated than we currently require, nor that they have any more
consistency than is required for us to acquire the language which determines
these concepts. (And the amount of time wasted in philosophical analysis over
the last half century in an endeavour to show that this case counts as
knowledge and that case counts as mere belief ± to take just one example ±
shows how much the Platonism which underlies the programme of philosophical
analysis has corrupted the discipline.)
I ought not to conclude without saying that this wellproduced book is a
pleasure to read. Stroll writes in an elegant and civilized manner. It is a
pleasing fact about contemporary philosophythat the books which one enjoys and
to which one returns are often written by thinkers who are not usually ranked
amongst the socalled superstars. Stroll is consistently thoughtprovoking. The
standard of argument varies but there is a freshness and individuality about
his approach which is very attractive. Stroll s heart is in the right place
even if too often it beats to the rhythm of his opponents.
N OT E S
1 SeeJ.O.Urmson s classicpaper `OnGrading , inA.G.N.Flew(ed.), Logic and
Language, second series (Oxford: Blackwell, 1959). 2 E.M.Curley, Descartes
against the Sceptics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1978), p.48. 3 Bernard Williams,
Descartes; the Project of Pure Enquiry (Harmondsworth: Pelican
Books, 1978), App.
Received 30 October 1998
R. A. Sharpe, Department of Philosophy, University of Wales Lampeter, Lampeter,
Ceredigion SA48 7ED, UK.Email: R.A.Sharpe at Lamp.ac.UK
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list