[Paleopsych] TLS: Juliet Clutton-Brock: Factory farm ethics
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Wed Nov 30 23:24:06 UTC 2005
Juliet Clutton-Brock: Factory farm ethics
The Times Literary Supplement, 5.11.9
http://www.the-tls.co.uk/this_week/story.aspx?story_id=2112505
HUNTERS, HERDERS, AND HAMBURGERS
The past and future of human-animal relationships
Richard W. Bulliet
256pp. | Columbia University Press. $27.50; distributed in the UK by
Wiley. £18. | 0 231 13076 7
IN DEFENSE OF ANIMALS
The second wave
Peter Singer, editor
248pp. | Oxford: Blackwell £50 (paperback, £9.99). US $59.95
(paperback, $21.95). | 1 4051 1940 3
ANIMAL ETHICS
Robert Garner
189pp. | Oxford: Polity. £55 (paperback, 315.99). US $59.95
(paperback, $24.95). | 0 7456 3078 2
In Hunters, Herders, and Hamburgers, Richard W. Bulliet divides the
history of human-animal relations into four eras: separation, the time
when he presumes that humans or pre-human hominids became self-aware
as a species; predomestic, the period of hunter-gathering; domestic,
lasting from the Neolithic until, say, 1900, when around 40 per cent
of US citizens lived on farms and were self-sufficient on their land;
post-domestic, our present age of mass production when only about 2
per cent of US citizens live on farms. These divisions are used by
Bulliet as a basis for his hypothesis that the changing patterns of
how humans perceive animals, both wild and domestic, are a reflection
of the development of societies over time. However, the divisions
might have been easier to understand if domestic had been named the
"age of the home farm" and post-domestic the "age of the factory
farm".
In Bulliet's view, domestic societies lived close to the land, and
people took for granted the killing of farm animals and had few moral
qualms about consuming animal products. In early domestic societies,
the sacrificial killing of animals was common practice, while later,
in Europe, blood sports such as bear- and bull-
baiting were immensely popular. In post-domestic societies, there has
been a great change, and with the divorce from the realities of
keeping, breeding and killing livestock, people experience feelings of
guilt, shame and disgust when they think about the industrial
processes to which domestic animals are subjected. In future, as
urbanism spreads, post-domestic people will be separated increasingly
from live animals and they will gain their only experiences of them
from print and from the electronic media.
Bulliet has an impressive knowledge of archaeozoology and the history
of human relationships with animals, and he ranges over a great
diversity of topics from current theories about the process of
domestication in the prehistoric period to the modern creation of pet
cemeteries and pet-loss counselling. The difficulty for the reader is
that a plethora of anecdotes and legends areis cited and they are
described with such exuberance, and often at considerable length, so
it is difficult to follow the trend of the author's many ideas.
Richard Bulliet is more concerned with human attitudes and behaviour
in relation to animals than he
is with how to prevent cruelty to animals, but he does recognize the
urgent, worldwide need to remedy the appalling standards of animal
welfare that predominate in our post-domestic (factory farm) age.
Public objection to cruelty to farm animals has only gathered momentum
in the past half-century, but it has had a long history in science and
medical research, dating from anger against the philosophical
pronouncements of René
Descartes (1596-1650) and early experiments that were carried out on
live animals. These raised horrified comments such as that of Dr
Johnson, who wrote in 1758: "Among the inferiour professors of medical
knowledge, is a race of wretches, whose lives are only varied by
varieties of cruelty; whose favourite amusement is to nail dogs to
tables and open them alive".
The explosion of interest in science, during the nineteenth century,
of necessity led to a great increase in experiments on live animals,
before anaesthetics were in widespread use. From 1875, as a result of
sustained opposition by the public, an anti-vivisection bill was put
before Parliament, which was debated and then led to a Royal
Commission, on which T. H. Huxley served as Counsel for Science.
Arguments waged to and fro, very much as they have in the past twenty
years, with this comment being made by Huxley in a letter to Darwin on
January 22, 1875: "If physiological experimentation is put down by
law, hunting, fishing, and shooting, against which a much better case
can be made out, will soon follow".
It was to be more than a hundred years before debate on this topic was
renewed with such vigour, and it may be claimed that Peter Singer has
been one of its chief protagonists. The first edition of In Defence of
Animals was published in 1985 and contained a large number of short
essays by a diversity of authors, from a lawyer to academic
philosophers to political lobbyists, and its aim, as stated by Singer,
itsthe book'sits editor, was to provide a platform for the new
animal-liberation movement. It certainly succeeded, as was shown by
the majorcoup that was recently achieved, when the flotation of
Huntingdon Life Sciences as a company on the New York Stock Exchange
was postponed forty-five minutes before trading began. The new edition
has a larger and more attractive format, American spelling, and only
one unchanged essay. The final chapter is boldly named "Ten Points for
Activists"; it is a revision by Singer of the chapter in the first
edition, by the late Henry Spira, named "Fighting To Win", and gives
measured advice to those who wish to campaign for animals. As their
long-running battle against Huntingdon Life Sciences shows, activists
are still more concerned with the fate of animals in scientific and
medical establishments than they are with the welfare of farm animals.
There are historical as well as economic and political reasons for
this, but not biological ones, for the iniquities and cruelties of the
factory farm far outnumber those of medical research, as cogently
described in several harrowing essays both in In Defense
of Animals and in Robert Garner's new book, Animal Ethics.
Garner succeeds in presenting a clearly written and eminently readable
account of present thinking on the moral status of animals, and
whether those mammals that have cognitive abilities approaching those
of humans, such as the great apes, should be regarded as full persons.
The concept of personhood is outlined both by Garner and in Peter
Singer's collection. Both books discuss whether full personhood is
morally significant and what it means for the treatment of those with
and without it. Garner asks, if animals are considered to be moral
agents, whether humans are then morally obliged to intervene to
protect animals when they are attacked by other animals, for example
when a wolf attacks a sheep. A recent letter in the Independent
(September 2, 2005) from D. J. Walker pointed to the political
implications of this: "I wonder if the resettlement of the grey wolf
to control the red deer and roe deer populations in Scotland might
contravene the law against hunting with dogs. Are wild packs
specifically exempted, or are their activities not regarded in law as
cruel?". On the other side of the personhood discussion, it could be
argued that it is justified for humans to exploit animals because
animals exploit each other: nature is red in tooth and claw, and as
humans are part of nature, they are entitled to behave in this way
too. This argument that humans are part of nature has been used to
contend (for example, by Stephen Budiansky in The Covenant of the
Wild, 1992) that the enfolding of wild animals such as wolves, sheep
and horses into human societies andwith their subsequent
domestication, was a natural process from which the species benefited
by their great increase in numbers. This can be easily turned into the
facile mantra that these animals chose domestication and therefore it
is all right for humans to exploit them. In 1776, Dr Johnson pondered
on this:
"There is much talk of misery which we cause to the brute creation;
but they are recompensed by existence. If they were not useful to man,
and therefore protected by him, they would not be nearly so numerous .
. . . But the question is, whether the animals who endure such
sufferings of various kinds, for the service and entertainment of man,
would accept of existence upon the terms on which they have it."
It is clear that by awarding moral status or indeed equal rights to
animals and humans, the contortions in thinking would be boundless,
but even without this the moral maze is probably intractable. To give
one crucial example, mentioned by Robert Garner, in Britain to keep a
bird in a cage where it cannot spread its wings is illegal under the
1911 Protection of Animals Act; but this is precisely what is allowed
for poultry in battery cages. Sadly, it is unlikely that even the best
efforts of those responsible for finalizing the forthcoming Animal
Welfare Bill will be able to do much to alleviate the horrors of the
factory farm.
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list