[Paleopsych] City Journal: (Foucault) Theodore Dalrymple: In the Asylum
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Sat Oct 15 01:15:38 UTC 2005
Theodore Dalrymple: In the Asylum
http://www.city-journal.org/html/15_3_oh_to_be.html
2005 Summer
The Victorian lunatic asylums of my city were magnificent, from the
purely architectural point of view. Municipal pride, manifested by
artistic embellishment without utilitarian purpose, shone out from
them. They were built on generous grounds in what were then rural
areas, outside the city bounds, on the theory that rustic peace had a
healing effect upon fractured minds--and also that remoteness would
protect the sane of the city from distressing contact with the insane.
The city expanded and soon engulfed the asylums, but the grounds
remained, often the only islands of green in a sea of soot and red
brick. These grounds, right up until the asylums closed, were tended
with a care that spoke of love and devotion.
For all who worked in them, the asylums provided a genuine sense of
community. Indeed, by the time of their closure, they were the only
real communities for miles around, the surrounding society having been
smashed into atoms. They held annual cricket matches and other
sporting contests on their spacious lawns, and hosted summer and
Christmas balls. The staff were often second- or third-generation
employees, and the institution was central to their lives.
The patients benefited from the stability; the asylum was a little
world in which they could behave as strangely as they pleased without
anyone caring too much. They were free of the mockery and disdain with
which people elsewhere would greet their strange demeanor, gestures,
and ideas: for in the asylum, the strange was normal. Within its
bounds, there was no stigma.
But of course, there was a very dark side as well. Physical
conditions, especially for those patients so chronically ill that the
wards were in effect their homes, were appalling. There was no
privacy, with beds sometimes packed so closely together that no one
could walk between them. The smell of urine so deeply impregnated the
furnishings and floors of the dayrooms that it seemed ineradicable
(not that anyone tried to eradicate it). The stodgy food and physical
inactivity meant that chronic constipation was universal; and most
patients looked as if they had filtered their food through their
shirts, blouses, and sweaters. Aimless wandering in the corridors was
the principal recreation for many patients, who rarely saw a doctor,
therapeutic impotence being more or less taken for granted.
Individuals had lived in these conditions for more than half a
century; and it was possible until the late 1980s to find women who
had been committed to the asylums in the 1920s merely for having borne
illegitimate children. As in the Soviet Union (though to a far less
sinister degree), deviance was sometimes labeled madness and treated
accordingly.
Most of the staff were kindly and well-meaning, but, as in any
situation in which some human beings have unsupervised care of and
power over others, opportunities for sadism abounded. Usually these
were minor: I often saw nurses denying cigarettes to patients, telling
them to come back in a few minutes, for no other reason than the
pleasure of exerting power over a fellow being. But from time to time,
far worse cruelty would surface, always hushed up in the name of
institutional morale. This was easily done, since very few outside the
asylum concerned themselves with what went on inside.
For most of their existence, the asylums were custodial rather than
therapeutic institutions. Their methods now strike us as laughably
crude. One asylum doctor published a memoir just after World War I in
which he described how he and his colleagues treated suicidal
melancholics and agitated paranoiacs. They sat the melancholics
against a wall, placing a bench in front of them to prevent them from
moving, while an attendant watched them to ensure that they did not do
away with themselves. Croton oil, a very powerful laxative, subdued
the agitation of the paranoiacs, who became so preoccupied with the
movement of their bowels that they had no time or energy left to act
upon the content of their delusions.
Attempts at cures were often more desperate than well-advised. One of
the asylums of my city had the best-equipped operating theater of its
time, where an enthusiastic psychiatrist partially eviscerated his
patients and also removed all their teeth, on the theory that madness
was caused by a chronic but undetected and subclinical infection
(called "focal sepsis") in the organs that he removed. Later, a
visiting neurosurgeon used the theater to perform lobotomies on
patients who were scarcely aware of what was being done to them.
Doctors also tried more "advanced" treatments, such as insulin coma
therapy, in which they gave schizophrenic patients insulin to lower
their blood sugars to the point at which they became unconscious,
sometimes with fatal effect.
It was not difficult, then, to present asylums as chambers of horrors,
where bizarre sadistic rituals were carried out for reasons
unconnected with beneficent medical endeavor. And it so happened that
one of the most powerful critics of both the asylum system and
psychiatry as a whole--powerful in the sense of having had the
greatest overall effect--published his attack in 1961, not long after
the introduction of medications so efficacious in the treatment of
psychosis that the asylum populations had already begun to decline, as
patients were discharged back into the outside world. The name of the
critic was Michel Foucault, and within a few years his Madness and
Civilization had spawned an entire movement, though of somewhat
disparate elements.
Foucault was not so much concerned by the cases of abuse or the poor
conditions in asylums, as a mere reformer might have been. In the
tortuous prose then typical of French intellectuals, he was concerned
to assert that the separation of the mad from the sane, both
physically and as a matter of classification, was neither
intellectually justified nor motivated by beneficence. Instead, it was
an instance of the exertion of power by the rising bourgeoisie, which
needed a disciplined and compliant workforce to fuel its economic
system and was therefore increasingly intolerant of deviance--not only
of conduct but of thought. It therefore locked deviants away in what
Foucault called "the great incarceration" of the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries, of which the asylums of the Victorian era were a
late manifestation.
In Foucault's Nietzschean vision, all human institutions--even, or
especially, those of avowedly beneficent intent--are expressions of
the will to power, because such a will underlies all human activity.
It is not really surprising, then, if asylums had turned into nothing
but chambers of horrors: for psychiatry, and indeed the whole of
medicine, to the rest of which Foucault soon turned his undermining
attention, were not enterprises to liberate mankind from some of its
travails--enterprises that inevitably committed errors en route to
knowledge and enlightenment--but expressions of the will to power of
the medical profession. The fact that this will was cloaked under an
official ideology of benevolence made it only the more dangerous and
sinister. This will needed to be unmasked, so that mankind could
liberate itself and live in the anarchic Dionysian mode that Foucault
favored. (A sadomasochistic homosexual, the French philosopher later
lived out his fantasies in San Francisco, and died of AIDS as a
result.)
Foucault inspired subsequent critics of psychiatry, of varying degrees
of scholarliness, rationality, and clarity of exposition. Among the
best was the influential historian Andrew Scull, whose history of the
origins of asylums, Museums of Madness, nevertheless implied that the
arrogation of insanity to the purview of doctors in the eighteenth
century did not grow out of any natural connection between the
phenomena of madness and the endeavor of medicine--still less out of
the practical ability of doctors of the time to cure madness (witness
their failure in the case of George III)--but on the medical
profession's entrepreneurial drive to increase its influence and
income. The fact that the mad eventually came under the care of the
medical profession was thus an historical accident, the result of the
shrewd maneuvering of the doctors: some other group--the clergymen,
for example, or the tailors--might have occupied the same position had
they maneuvered as successfully. Founded on so illegitimate a basis,
psychiatry was by implication a totally false undertaking.
This argument overlooks a few obvious facts, however. What could have
been said of madness could have been said of dysentery and
pneumonia--that the doctors of the time had no power to cure them and
that therefore these diseases were not properly the province of
physicians and might just as well have been handled by tinkers or
topographers. If the Foucauldian style of thought had prevailed at
earlier times, with that mind-set's failure to understand
imaginatively what is required to go from a state of complete
ignorance to one of partial knowledge, and how it is often necessary
to act in a state of ignorance, no one would ever have discovered
anything about the cause or treatment of disease.
Moreover, the connection between madness and medicine is not entirely
arbitrary and unfounded, as Scull suggested (though in my opinion the
scope of psychiatry has since expanded illegitimately, especially in
the grotesque overprescription of psychotropic medication). The
eighteenth-century doctors had in this respect a better grasp of
reality than Professor Scull, for organic conditions leading to
madness and dementia must have been very common at the time. It has
been plausibly suggested (though not conclusively proved) that George
III was suffering from porphyria, possibly exacerbated by lead
poisoning, for instance, and at the end of the nineteenth century, up
to a quarter of the population of the asylums was suffering from
general paralysis of the insane, the last stage of syphilis. Dare I
mention that were it not for modern medicine, I myself would long ago
have ended up in an asylum, one of those apathetic creatures that the
physiognomists of madness in the nineteenth century so eloquently
portrayed in their drawings, because I suffer from hypothyroidism,
which is the most common of all endocrine diseases and which untreated
can lead to madness and finally to dementia?
Another rhetorically powerful critic of psychiatry, also influenced by
Foucault, was R. D. Laing, himself a psychiatrist. It was he who, in
the 1960s and 1970s, gave currency to the idea that madness was an
alternative, and in some ways superior, way of being in the world:
that madness was in fact true sanity, and sanity true madness, insofar
as the world itself was quite mad in its political, social, and
domestic arrangements. According to Laing, it was the unequal power
within families, and the distorted communications to which this
inequality gave rise, that caused the condition in young people known
as schizophrenia. To hospitalize them and treat them against their
will was thus to punish them for the sins of their parents and to
maintain an unjust social order at the same time.
This view became extremely popular in an era that uncritically
criticized all institutions. The psychotic came to be viewed by
right-thinking people as victims of injustice rather than as sufferers
from illness (an attitude reinforced when it was discovered that young
men of Jamaican origin living in Britain had a rate of schizophrenia
six, seven, or eight times that of young white men). What was required
was not treatment but restitution.
These ideas paved the way for an ill-conceived and hasty
deinstitutionalization of the mentally ill. Thanks to effective
treatments, the numbers requiring to be institutionalized were
declining anyway; politicians hoped to save money by
deinstitutionalization and were all too willing to believe that the
mentally ill could be managed almost without any institutions
whatever; and finally, criticisms of the Foucauldian mold--that
society had no right to impose restraint upon the mad--entered common
consciousness. Madmen had a right to wander the streets, and other
citizens had the duty to put up with it.
The asylums of my city closed within a few short years. The patients
were sent to live in what bureaucrats insisted upon calling "the
community," because of that term's connotations of warmth and welcome.
With varying degrees of assistance and supervision, they were expected
to live independently; they were given their autonomy, whether they
wanted it or not. Many coped adequately with their newfound freedom,
but many did not. And meanwhile, hospital provision for the mentally
ill declined to such an extent, both for budgetary and ideological
reasons (hospital admission was to be avoided at all costs, in a
fetishistic kind of way, irrespective of the logic of the individual
case), that every time it became imperatively necessary to admit a
psychiatric patient, the entire system experienced a crisis. Madmen
were left in police cells for days on end while hospital beds were
found for them; sometimes, not a single such bed could be found in an
area with a population of 4 or 5 million.
Every day in my work as a prison doctor, I witnessed the effect of
this lack of provision. Ironically, the splendid new hospital wing of
the prison, built with few expenses spared, rose on the grounds of an
asylum that had just been closed down; but inside the hospital, we
were re-creating the conditions of eighteenth-century Bedlam. Modern
walls do not a modern hospital make. Unearthly screams rent the air;
foul smells offended the nostrils. Madmen threw their clothes through
the windows, started fires in their cells, tore up their sheets,
wrapped towels around their heads, angrily addressed their
hallucinatory interlocutors while standing stark naked on their beds,
refused all food as poisoned, and spat at passersby. All that was
lacking were visitors from the outside world who had paid their
pennies to laugh at the lunatics; I suggested that we re-institute
this great tradition to improve the prison's finances.
The cases would go like this: a madman would commit an offense--say, a
completely unprovoked assault on a person in the street (unprovoked,
that is, from the victim's point of view; the perpetrator would
believe that the victim had been threatening or insulting him). The
police would arrest him and take him to the police station. They would
recognize that he was mad--his speech would be rambling and
incoherent, he spoke of things that were not, and his behavior was
completely beyond the bounds of reason. They would call a doctor, who
would say that yes, the man was mad, but that no, he could not be
admitted to a hospital to be treated, because there were no beds
available.
The police then faced a dilemma. They could either release the man
back into the community, whose sense of social solidarity he had so
reinforced by his unprovoked attack on a random stranger, or they
could charge him and put him before the courts. Sometimes they would
do the one, sometimes the other. I have known lunatics released from
police custody who clearly had intended to kill their victims in the
street (and were handed back the weapons with which they intended to
do it), because a policeman did not want to charge a man who was so
obviously not responsible for his actions.
At other times, depending on who knows what factors, the police would
bring the man before the courts, where a system of psychiatric
screening had been set up. Theoretically, the accused found to be
psychiatrically unwell by the examining nurse would be diverted from
the criminal justice system into the psychiatric system. But the
nurse, knowing that no hospital beds would be available were she to
declare the accused mentally ill, and not wishing to accept the labor
of Hercules involved in trying to find such a bed, declares the madman
(so mad that it requires no expertise at all to detect his madness) to
be fully sane, or a malingerer, or to be currently under the influence
of marijuana, so that his madness will pass within a short time and
results from voluntary intoxication, which is no excuse under the law
for his crime. Thus the madman is remanded into custody; and the nurse
calms her conscience with the hope that the prison doctor will
recognize the man's madness and will try to find a hospital bed for
him.
Unfortunately, things do not go smoothly in the prison. The doctor
cannot find a hospital bed for his mad patient; the psychiatrists
outside the prison consider that the patient is now in a place of
safety--the prison--where he will not be deprived of medical
attention, and he is therefore of lower priority for a hospital bed
than a lunatic still at large in the community. He is thus kept, often
for months, in the prison on remand.
As the law now stands in Britain, prison doctors are not permitted to
give treatment against a patient's will, except under the direst
emergency, for fear that they might abuse such power and forcibly
sedate whomever they choose contrary to the patient's human rights.
Hence psychotic patients are now kept in prison hospitals for months
without any treatment whatsoever, thus taking part in an interesting
if not altogether pleasing experiment in the natural history of
psychosis, such as has not been conducted for many years.
Recently, for example, I observed a psychotic patient for several
weeks, who addressed the world night and day through his prison window
in words of muddled religious exaltation, who refused all food on the
grounds that it was poisoned, his flesh melting away before my eyes,
who attacked anyone who came within reach, and who painted religious
slogans on the walls of his cell with his own excrement, thus
imparting a nauseating feculent smell to the entire hospital.
It might, of course, be alleged that he behaved in so disturbed a
fashion because he was incarcerated, and that his conduct was (in the
opinion of R. D. Laing) a meaningful and enlightened response to his
terrible social situation, and that he, of all the 1,400 prisoners in
the prison, was acting in the most appropriate way under the
circumstances. But this would be not only to ignore his medical
history but also the fact that he was incarcerated in the first place
because he had viciously and without provocation attacked a
79-year-old woman in a church, injuring her badly while reciting
verses from the Bible, which suggests that his disturbed mental state
preceded his incarceration and was not a consequence of it.
I checked the situation with lawyers. Although he had a fully
documented history of psychosis and an entirely favorable response to
treatment, attested to by both doctors and relatives (who said that
when treated he was a pleasant and intelligent man), I was not
entitled, in the name of human rights, to treat him against his will.
In the name of human rights, therefore, the prison officers and the
other prisoners had to endure weeks of revolting air, as well as
disturbed nights in which sleep was all but impossible, while he lived
in conditions that Hogarth might well have painted with justified
moral fury.
The doctors to whom I proposed to send the patient accepted the
conditions in which he lived with Buddha-like calm that would have
been admirable had the suffering been theirs. Only the prison
officers, among the most despised of all public servants, seemed to be
moved by the scandal of the situation. The doctors, by contrast, were
now so inured to such situations that they accepted it as normal and
nothing to get excited about. The shortage of beds and the
administrative difficulties that this shortage caused had steadily
eroded their common humanity. It was only when I threatened to expose
the scandal publicly and had taken photographs of the man's cell and
said I would send them to the government minister responsible for
prisons (a proceeding completely against the rules, but supported by
the prison warden, who did not want his prison turned into a surrogate
lunatic asylum) that the man was finally found a place in a hospital,
where he could be treated.
Of course, Foucault might have put a completely different construction
on the outrage of the prison officers and the desire of the man's
relatives for him to be treated and returned to normality. He might
have interpreted all this as an intolerant refusal to accept the man's
alternative way of life, a refusal even to try to interpret the
meaning of the communications that he coded in his own excrement. For
Foucault, their concern, couched in the terms of humanity, concealed a
drive for power and domination, used to produce conformity to
debilitating and dehumanizing bourgeois standards. But such an
interpretation would surely mean that common humanity and a feeling
for others are qualities whose very possibility he would radically
deny: that the only relations that could exist between men are those
of power, and that all else is illusion.
I am aware that hard cases make bad law, but I could cite many such
cases as the one above; of cases, for example, where doctors have
changed their diagnoses in order to avoid the responsibility of
finding hospital beds for their patients, and where they have even
perjured themselves in court to evade that responsibility, to the
great detriment of the patient and the safety of society alike. These
are now part of everyday practice.
The shortage of beds, brought about by the desire to make financial
savings in the context of an ideological assault on the notion of
psychiatric illness, has corrupted doctors and nurses by slow but
inexorable steps.
I am also aware that many horror stories could be told of doctors who
have been overzealous (to put it mildly) in their attempts to cure
their patients or to spread their fields of operations to their own
material and social advantage. There is no simple formula for avoiding
the Scylla of zealotry on the one hand and the Charybdis of
abandonment of responsibility on the other. The art is long, life is
short, the occasion fleeting, and judgment difficult. But the
difficulty must be faced.
One thing is certain: that Foucault and his ilk are no guides to how
to treat a man like the one I have described (and such as I have come
across every day). Should he have been let free, to continue his
Dionysian assaults on defenseless old ladies, on the grounds that they
were life-enhancing? I cannot see that this represents anything but a
preference for barbarism.
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list