[Paleopsych] CHE: Jürgen Habermas and Post-Secular Societies
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Mon Sep 26 23:54:06 UTC 2005
Jürgen Habermas and Post-Secular Societies
The Chronicle of Higher Education, 5.9.25
http://chronicle.com/weekly/v52/i05/05b01601.htm
By RICHARD WOLIN
Among 19th-century thinkers it was an uncontestable commonplace that
religion's cultural centrality was a thing of the past. For Georg
Hegel, following in the footsteps of the Enlightenment, religion had
been surpassed by reason's superior conceptual precision. In The
Essence of Christianity (1841), Ludwig Feuerbach depicted the
relationship between man and divinity as a zero-sum game. In his view,
the stress on godliness merely detracted from the sublimity of human
ends. In one of his youthful writings, Karl Marx, Feuerbach's most
influential disciple, famously dismissed religion as "the opium of the
people." Its abolition, Marx believed, was a sine qua non for human
betterment. Friedrich Nietzsche got to the heart of the matter by
having his literary alter ego, the brooding prophet Zarathustra,
brusquely declaim, "God is dead," thereby pithily summarizing what
many educated Europeans were thinking but few had the courage actually
to say. And who can forget Nietzsche's searing characterization of
Christianity as a "slave morality," a plebeian belief system
appropriate for timorous conformists but unsuited to the creation of a
future race of domineering Übermenschen? True to character, the only
representatives of Christianity Nietzsche saw fit to praise were those
who could revel in a good auto-da-fé -- Inquisition stalwarts like
Ignatius Loyola.
Twentieth-century characterizations of belief were hardly more
generous. Here, one need look no further than the title of Freud's
1927 treatise on religion: The Future of an Illusion.
Today, however, there are omnipresent signs of a radical change in
mentality. In recent years, in both the United States and the
developing world, varieties of religious fundamentalism have had a
major political impact. As Democratic presidential hopefuls Howard
Dean and John Kerry learned the hard way, politicians who are
perceived as faithless risk losing touch with broad strata of the
electorate.
Are contemporary philosophers up to the challenge of explaining and
conceptualizing these striking recent developments? After all, what
Freud, faithfully reflecting the values of the scientific age,
cursorily dismissed as illusory seems to have made an unexpected and
assertive comeback -- one that shows few signs of abating anytime
soon.
Jürgen Habermas may be the living philosopher most likely to succeed
where angels, and their detractors, fear to tread. Following Jacques
Derrida's death last October, it would seem that Habermas has justly
inherited the title of the world's leading philosopher. Last year he
won the prestigious Kyoto Prize for Arts and Philosophy (previous
recipients include Karl Popper and Paul Ricoeur), capping an eventful
career replete with honors as well as a number of high-profile public
debates.
The centerpiece of Habermas's moral philosophy is "discourse ethics,"
which takes its inspiration from Immanuel Kant's categorical
imperative. For Kant, to count as moral, actions must pass the test of
universality: The actor must be able to will that anyone in a similar
situation should act in the same way. According to Kant, lying and
stealing are immoral insofar as they fall beneath the universalization
threshold; only at the price of grave self-contradiction could one
will that lying and stealing become universal laws. Certainly, we can
envisage a number of exceptional situations where we could conceivably
justify lying or stealing. In Kant's example, at your door is a man
intent on murdering your loved one and inquiring as to her
whereabouts. Or what if you were too poor to purchase the medicine
needed to save your spouse's life?
In the first case you might well think it would be permissible to lie;
and in the second case, to steal. Yet on both counts Kant is
immovable. An appeal to circumstances might well complicate our
decision making. It might even elicit considerable public sympathy for
otherwise objectionable conduct. But it can in no way render an
immoral action moral. It is with good reason that Kant calls his
imperative a categorical one, for an imperative that admits of
exceptions is really no imperative at all.
Habermas's approach to moral philosophy is Kantian, although he takes
exception to the solipsistic, egological framework Kant employs.
Habermas believes that, in order to be convincing, moral reasoning
needs a broader, public basis. Discourse ethics seeks to offset the
limitations of the Kantian approach. For Habermas, the give and take
of argumentation, as a learning process, is indispensable. Through
communicative reason we strive for mutual understanding and learn to
assume the standpoint of the other. Thereby we also come to appreciate
the narrowness of our own individual perspective. Discourse ethics
proposes that those actions are moral that could be justified in an
open-ended and genuine public dialogue. Its formula suggests that
"only those norms can claim to be valid that meet (or could meet) with
the appro-val of all affected in their capacity as participants in a
practical discourse."
Until recently Habermas was known as a resolutely secular thinker. On
occasion his writings touched upon religious subjects or themes. But
these confluences were exceptions that proved the rule.
Yet a few years ago the tonality of his work began to change ever so
subtly. In fall 2001 Habermas was awarded the prestigious Peace Prize
of the German Publishers and Booksellers Association. The title of his
acceptance speech, "Faith and Knowledge," had a palpably theological
ring. The remarks, delivered shortly after the September 11 terrorist
attacks, stressed the importance of mutual toleration between secular
and religious approaches to life.
Last year Habermas engaged in a high-profile public dialogue with
Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger -- who, on April 19, was named as Pope John
Paul II's successor -- at the cardinal's behest. A number of the
philosopher's left-wing friends and followers were taken aback by his
willingness to have a dialogue with one of Europe's most conservative
prelates. In 2002 Habermas had published In Defense of Humanity, an
impassioned critique of the risks of biological engineering and human
cloning. It was this text in particular, in which the philosopher
provided an eloquent defense of the right to a unique human identity
-- a right that cloning clearly imperils -- that seems to have piqued
the cardinal's curiosity and interest. Yet if one examines the
trajectory of Habermas's intellectual development, the Ratzinger
exchange seems relatively unexceptional.
Glance back at Habermas's philosophical chef d'oeuvre, the two-volume
Theory of Communicative Action (1981), and you'll find that one of his
key ideas is the "linguistification of the sacred" (Versprachlichung
des Sakrals). By this admittedly cumbersome term, Habermas asserts
that modern notions of equality and fairness are secular distillations
of time-honored Judeo-Christian precepts. The "contract theory" of
politics, from which our modern conception of "government by consent
of the governed" derives, would be difficult to conceive apart from
the Old Testament covenants. Similarly, our idea of the intrinsic
worth of all persons, which underlies human rights, stems directly
from the Christian ideal of the equality of all men and women in the
eyes of God. Were these invaluable religious sources of morality and
justice to atrophy entirely, it is doubtful whether modern societies
would be able to sustain this ideal on their own.
In a recent interview Habermas aptly summarized those insights: "For
the normative self-understanding of modernity, Christianity has
functioned as more than just a precursor or a catalyst. Universalistic
egalitarianism, from which sprang the ideals of freedom and a
collective life in solidarity, the autonomous conduct of life and
emancipation, the individual morality of conscience, human rights, and
democracy, is the direct legacy of the Judaic ethic of justice and the
Christian ethic of love."
Three years ago the MIT Press published Religion and Rationality:
Essays on Reason, God, and Modernity, an illuminating collection of
Habermas's writings on religious themes. Edited and introduced by the
philosopher Eduardo Mendieta, of the State University of New York at
Stony Brook, the anthology concludes with a fascinating interview in
which the philosopher systematically clarifies his views on a variety
of religious areas. (A companion volume, The Frankfurt School on
Religion: Key Writings by the Major Thinkers, also edited by Mendieta,
was published in 2004 by Routledge.)
On the one hand, religion's return -- Habermas, perhaps with the
American situation foremost in mind, goes so far as to speak of the
emergence of "post-secular societies" -- presents us with undeniable
dangers and risks. While theodicy has traditionally provided men and
women with consolation for the harsh injustices of fate, it has also
frequently taught them to remain passively content with their lot. It
devalues worldly success and entices believers with the promise of
eternal bliss in the hereafter. Here the risk is that religion may
encourage an attitude of social passivity, thereby contravening
democracy's need for an active and engaged citizenry. To wit, the
biblical myth of the fall perceives secular history as a story of
decline or perdition from which little intrinsic good may emerge.
On the other hand, laissez-faire's success as a universally revered
economic model means that, today, global capitalism's triumphal march
encounters few genuine oppositional tendencies. In that regard,
religion, as a repository of transcendence, has an important role to
play. It prevents the denizens of the modern secular societies from
being overwhelmed by the all-encompassing demands of vocational life
and worldly success. It offers a much-needed dimension of otherness:
The religious values of love, community, and godliness help to offset
the global dominance of competitiveness, acquisitiveness, and
manipulation that predominate in the vocational sphere. Religious
convictions encourage people to treat each other as ends in themselves
rather than as mere means.
One of Habermas's mentors, the Frankfurt School philosopher Max
Horkheimer, once observed that "to salvage an unconditional meaning"
-- one that stood out as an unqualified Good -- "without God is a
futile undertaking." As a stalwart of the Enlightenment, Habermas
himself would be unlikely to go that far. But he might consider
Horkheimer's adage a timely reminder of the risks and temptations of
all-embracing secularism. Habermas stressed in a recent public lecture
"the force of religious traditions to articulate moral intuitions with
regard to communal forms of a dignified human life." As forceful and
persuasive as our secular philosophical precepts might be -- the idea
of human rights, for example -- from time to time they benefit from
renewed contact with the nimbus of their sacral origins.
Last April Habermas presented a more systematic perspective on
religion's role in contemporary society at an international conference
on "Philosophy and Religion" at Poland's Lodz University. One of the
novelties of Habermas's Lodz presentation, "Religion in the Public
Sphere," was the commendable idea that "toleration" -- the bedrock of
modern democratic culture -- is always a two-way street. Not only must
believers tolerate others' beliefs, including the credos and
convictions of nonbelievers; it falls due to disbelieving secularists,
similarly, to appreciate the convictions of religiously motivated
fellow citizens. From the standpoint of Habermas's "theory of
communicative action," this stipulation suggests that we assume the
standpoint of the other. It would be unrealistic and prejudicial to
expect that religiously oriented citizens wholly abandon their most
deeply held convictions upon entering the public sphere where, as a
rule and justifiably, secular reasoning has become our default
discursive mode. If we think back, for instance, to the religious
idealism that infused the civil-rights movement of the 1950s and
1960s, we find an admirable example of the way in which a biblical
sense of justice can be fruitfully brought to bear on contemporary
social problems.
The philosopher who addressed these issues most directly and
fruitfully in recent years was John Rawls. In a spirit of collegial
solidarity, Habermas, in his Lodz paper, made ample allusion to
Rawlsian ideals. Perhaps Rawls's most important gloss on religion's
role in modern politics is his caveat or "proviso" that, to gain a
reasonable chance of public acceptance, religious reasons must
ultimately be capable of being translated into secular forms of
argumentation. In the case of public officials -- politicians and the
judiciary, for example -- Rawls raises the secular bar still higher.
He believes that, in their political language, there is little room
for an open and direct appeal to nonsecular reasons, which, in light
of the manifest diversity of religious beliefs, would prove extremely
divisive. As Habermas affirms, echoing Rawls: "This stringent demand
can only be laid at the door of politicians, who within state
institutions are subject to the obligation to remain neutral in the
face of competing worldviews." But if that stringent demand is on the
politician, Habermas argues, "every citizen must know that only
secular reasons count beyond the institutional threshold that divides
the informal public sphere from parliaments, courts, ministries, and
administrations."
With his broad-minded acknowledgment of religion's special niche in
the spectrum of public political debate, Habermas has made an
indispensable stride toward defining an ethos of multicultural
tolerance. Without such a perspective, prospects for equitable global
democracy would seem exceedingly dim. The criterion for religious
belief systems that wish to have their moral recommendations felt and
acknowledged is the capacity to take the standpoint of the other. Only
those religions that retain the capacity to bracket or suspend the
temptations of theological narcissism -- the conviction that my
religion alone provides the path to salvation -- are suitable players
in our rapidly changing, post-secular moral and political universe.
Richard Wolin is a professor of history, comparative literature, and
political science at the Graduate Center of the City University of New
York. His books include The Seduction of Unreason: The Intellectual
Romance With Fascism From Nietzsche to Postmodernism (Princeton
University Press, 2004).
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list