[Paleopsych] Hedgehog: Thomas Cushman: The Sociology of Evil and The Destruction of Bosnia
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Sun Oct 17 15:58:31 UTC 2004
Thomas Cushman: The Sociology of Evil and The Destruction of Bosnia
The Hedgehog Review - Institute for Advanced Studies in Culture
http://etext.virginia.edu/etcbin/ot2www-hh?specfile=/texts/english/modeng/journals/hh.o2w&act=text&offset=306861&textreg=1&id=CusBosn2-2
In sociology, the subject of evil has been avoided, argues
Thomas Cushman, but the events of the twentieth century call for a
sociological grappling with the term. Cushman argues for looking at
evil as a form of social action, as something that human agents do,
and employs such a theory of evil in examining the war in Bosnia. He
focuses on the actions of Slobodan Milosevic, and the ways in which
Milosevic created an identity for himself that obscured the evil for
which he is responsible.
Thomas Cushman is Associate Professor and Chair of the Sociology
Department at Wellesley College, General Editor for the series
"Post-Communist Societies and Cultures," and Editor of Human Rights
Review. He has published numerous papers and books on Soviet society
and the Balkans and has co-edited, with Stjepan G. Mestrovic, This
Time We Knew: Western Responses to Genocide in Bosnia.
I
There is an apocalyptic quality to much writing on Bosnia, a
certain awestruck "homage to the extreme" as Michael Bernstein calls
it, which presumes that the answers to the question "why did this evil
happen?" lie outside the ken of normal human knowledge.[4]^2 Rather
than assume that events in Bosnia reveal some greater metaphysical
truth about evil or about some presumed stage of regression or
apocalypse in Western culture, I suggest that there might be a way to
offer at least some answer to the question of why those events
occurred and that such an answer lies in the analysis of the discrete
actions and interactions of specific agents within the contours of the
social time and space in which such agents exist. In this essay, I
would like to render the rhetorical question "why did it happen?" into
a sociological one: "what brought individual agents to do such things
and how were their acts facilitated by their social and cultural
environments?" The answer to this question requires a sociology of
evil that does not really exist, or if it does, only exists inchoately
in a few explicitly sociological works that attempt to present the
logic of evil and cruelty. My central purpose here is to work toward
the provision of such a theory. There are, to be sure, problems that
immediately arise in such a task.
As a moral concept, evil is an "ancient, and heavily freighted
term."[5]^3 The freight, in this case, is the baggage of morality,
metaphysics, emotions, essentialism, psychology--in short, all of the
things that sociology has defined itself against in the course of its
development as an autonomous discipline. Sociology is grounded in
philosophy. But if philosophy prior to the twentieth century seemed
inordinately concerned with the question of evil (as can be seen, for
example, in the works of Hegel, Kant, Hume, and Schopenhauer),
sociology is characterized by a conscious distancing of itself from
the term and a selective appropriation of ideas that fit the nascent
discipline's idea of human nature and the positive telos of human
evolution. Indeed, evil is sociology's Doppelgänger, always present,
but unwelcome, haunting the discipline and its quest for enlightenment
by calling to mind questions of metaphysics, agency, and the "dark
side" of human progress.
If evil appears at all in mainstream sociological theory, it
does so as a "falling away" from the good. Evil is always "not-A"
rather than "A." This moral stance--the idea that immorality,
deviance, and evil are "fallings away" from the good--is deeply
embedded in the history of sociological thought and has worked to
disestablish the ontological reality of evil in social theory and, by
way of that, to elide the presence of evil in social life. If evil
does appear as an autonomous and independent reality, it does so as a
sense of something negative about this or that social force rather
than as an explicit quality of social forces. While sociology aimed to
set itself apart from the question of evil (a question that was
central to philosophy), its concepts often convey a sense that, even
if evil is not specifically addressed, it is still present in the
world.
The first step in a sociology of evil, then, is to establish the
ontological status of evil. Without such a status, there is only an
emergent sociological evil or a purely relativistic conception, which
makes it impossible to make any statements about the actual existence
of something that we call evil.[6]^4 Pragmatic philosophy and "social
theory in the pragmatic mode" decry the effort to fix an idea of evil
over and above the language which is used by human beings to describe
the sensations they have of extreme phenomena. Yet after all that such
philosophies and theories have said and done to distance themselves
from the reality of evil, we are left--especially in consideration of
the brutal facts of the twentieth century--with a sense that there are
still things on earth that are not dreamt of in the philosophies of
those whose business it is to know the world.
To do evil is to intentionally inflict excessive pain and
suffering on someone else. What is evil about human actions is, in
Abigail Rosenthal's words, "that aspect of them that intentionally
obscures, disrupts, or deflects the ideal thread of plot in human
lives" and which does so in a way that is, from a normative
standpoint, excessive, cruel, or aberrant.[7]^5 Neil Smelser notes
that evil is "most appropriately applied to situations when force,
violence, and other forms of coercion exceed institutional or moral
limits."[8]^6 John Kekes sees evil actions as those which "cause
serious and morally unjustified harm to other human beings. [The] harm
is serious if it interferes with the functioning of a person as a
full-fledged agent."[9]^7
The second step in the sociology of evil is to raise the study
of evil to a level on par with those of other phenomena usually
studied by social scientists. Given the definition of evil offered
above, it is easy to see why it is important to establish an
operational idea of evil into the vocabulary of analysis of the
destruction of Bosnia. It was a particularly cruel and ferocious
event, one that was unimaginable in the context of late
twentieth-century Europe. Yet, in the dominant discourse on the war,
economic disparities, nationalism, historical precedent, and other
background factors are usually offered as the explanatory variables
that caused the war. These factors in and of themselves, though,
cannot explain some of the most salient aspects of the war: the
specific acts of barbarism and cruelty that characterize evil. Why did
soldiers rape and kill wives and children in front of husbands and
fathers and then leave the latter to live with the memory? Why did
soldiers destroy beautiful and ancient architectural monuments which
had no strategic value? Why were 12,000 people 1,800 of whom were
children--intentionally murdered in Sarajevo? The answers to these
questions can never be found purely in the analysis of political,
economic, or even cultural factors because, in the first instance,
politics, economics, and culture never do anything by themselves. It
is individuals who are enmeshed in politics, economics, and culture
who do things through or in relation to politics, economics, and
culture. That is to say, the true character of cruelty in Bosnia and
Herzegovina (and I think of cruelty in general) is to be found in the
acts of agents in relation to the structures that enable and constrain
them.
At base, evil is action, and as such the theory of evil that I
present here is a theory of action. It presents a view that contrasts
with those accounts that rely on some kind of historical or cultural
determinism to explain social outcomes in the Balkans: "The war was
caused by age-old hatreds." "The Serbs are products of a cruel
culture." "The Croats have a natural affinity for Nazism and
genocide." These views constitute the main parameters of both popular
and social science discourse on the war. They not only rely on crude
stereotypes and errors of fact, but also fail to capture the sense of
agency that is necessary in order to understand the specific qualities
of evil and cruelty. It was individuals who destroyed Bosnia, and they
did so not as automatons or dupes of historical or cultural forces,
but as willful agents who reflexively responded to the contours of
both local and global history, who reflexively adapted themselves to
the exigencies and contingencies of the unfolding present, and who
reflexively presented an ideal vision of the future that their actions
would, ideally, bring about.
II
While I want to develop a sociology of evil by way of reclaiming
what is important from the philosophy of evil, I do want to distance
myself from the idea of essential evil. The basis for a sociology of
evil is not metaphysics, but theories of social action. Evil is not an
essential quality of human beings, but is intentional action, the
result of the conscious reflection of actors and the willful decision
to do something severe to someone else.
If evil is agentic and intentional action that is reflexively
chosen, it should be fairly easy to account for it from the standpoint
of existing sociological theories of action and agency. We could just
adapt the latter to interpret actions that we consider evil. Yet,
sociological theorists of agency have, like sociological theorists in
general, displaced evil. This displacement has much to do with the
unbridled political optimism of the progenitors of the pragmatic
theories of social action. Action and reflexivity was, for these
thinkers and their later followers, always considered as progressive.
This development was ironic since such theories developed in a world
historical context in which it was rather evident that agents used the
infrastructure of modernity for nefarious rather than progressive
ends.
There is no logical or empirical reason to assume that
reflexivity is fundamentally oriented to optimistic, progressive,
Enlightenment ends. Indeed, if we are interested in looking at the
ways in which agency is enabled by the infrastructures of modernity,
we are likely to find our best examples in those whose acts would be
classified as "transgressive." The archetypal, ideal-type model of the
evil agent is to be found in the fictional characters of James Bond
stories: brilliant geniuses who have mastered modern technologies in
the service of grand anti-Enlightenment schemes. Such characters are
highly reflexive agents, perhaps even hyperreflexive. But the ends of
their agency and reflection are to maximize the pain and suffering of
others, to deliberately obscure the plot lines of others' lives
through creative intervention. This conception, of course, involves a
break with the view that reflexivity and moral progress go hand in
hand: reflexivity, in my view, is neither moral nor immoral,
progressive nor regressive, modern nor barbaric by nature. Rather,
evil is reflexive, creative, imaginative, adaptive, and cunning,
whatever its axiological ends, and especially so in relation to the
more technologically complex condition of modernity. To miss or
underestimate the reflexivity of evil is, I think, to fail to capture
the most important quality of evil. So what we need is a conception of
agency that allows us to examine evil as a form of social action.
Such a conception can be found in an imaginative article on the
nature of agency by Mustafa Emirbayer and Ann Mirsch, in which they
note that agency always proceeds in relation to past, present, and
future:
Actors are always living simultaneously in the past, the future,
and present, and adjusting to the various temporalities of their
empirical existence to one another (and to their empirical
circumstances) in more or less imaginative or reflective ways. They
continuously engage in patterns and repertoires from the past,
project hypothetical pathways forward in time, and adjust their
actions to the exigencies of emerging situations.[10]^8
This "relational pragmatics," as the authors refer to it, allows
us to conceive of agency as a function of a reflexive consciousness
that is oriented toward three temporal planes: past, present, and
future. The latter constitute a kind of "chordal triangle" which
actors "play" as they engage in reflexive social action.
In stressing the temporal bases of action, Emirbayer and
Mirsch's approach is much more sophisticated than that found in most
theories of agency and offers an imaginative basis for examining the
specific actions of agents under specific conditions of social time
and space. Their view is also especially useful for understanding
agency in the postmodern world in which past, future, and present are
made manifest to actors in many more ways, through many different
media. Curiously, though, the authors note that their analysis only
delineates the "analytical space within which reflective and morally
responsible action might be said to unfold."[11]^9 There is no
inherent reason why "relational pragmatics" should be considered
inherently positive and morally responsible. Indeed, it is the central
point of the present analysis that pragmatics are oriented in what
might be called, to invert Emirbayer and Mirsch's terminology,
"morally irresponsible ways." The connection between agency and moral
responsibility is not grounded in an empirical assessment of the range
of human activities, but rather is a product of the homage to the
idealism of pragmatic social theory. It is, in fact, deceiving to
restrict the analysis of action to those projects that are thought to
be morally constructive and progressive. The destruction of Bosnia is
only one recent case that illustrates that the forging of
un-democratic politics, the perpetration of cruel and ferocious acts,
and the masking of all the latter by the perpetrators and social
science interpreters is the product of highly reflexive agents who
insert themselves into the past, adapt to the present, and imagine a
future. Such cruelty does not just happen; it is made.
III
There is a saying in the Serbo-Croatian language: "riba se truje
od glave nadolje," which means that "fish rots from the head down."
The principle architects of the destruction of Bosnia--Serbian
elites--set into motion a whole process, a whole machinery of agents
who, in toto, effected the destruction of Bosnia. The Bosnian war was
perhaps the most widely covered war in history; phalanxes of
journalists were constantly on the scene to capture events as they
unfolded. The presence of these journalists was a major factor in the
reflexive considerations of the perpetrators of violence, and it is
through these media that we witnessed the destruction of Bosnia and
the reflexive accounts of the agents who effected that destruction and
provided a rationale for them. My data is the actual footage of these
figures by Western journalists and the "presentations of self" that
these elites put forth through local and global media. The words of
these agents provide indications of the ways in which they consciously
and reflexively played the past, present, and future as the basis for
their ongoing social actions. In this essay, I will focus on the
principal agent in the dissolution of Bosnia, Slobodan Milosevic.
Slobodan Milosevic did not create himself as a nationalist, but
actually inserted himself into an existing historical current of
Serbian concern about the encroachment of national minorities on
Serbs, particularly in the autonomous region of Kosovo. The special
importance of Kosovo as the place where the Serbs suffered defeat at
the hands of the "Turks" in 1389 is quite well known. But all through
Serbian history, Kosovo has been a special site of tension between
Albanians and Serbs; this tension had been exacerbated in the
nineteenth and twentieth centuries by patterns of out-migration of
Serbs and in-migration of Albanians.
This motif of Serbian nationalism ran through twentieth-century
Serbian history and found expression and intensification in later
pronouncements of Serbian intellectuals. In January 1986, two hundred
prominent Belgrade intellectuals signed a petition to the Yugoslav and
Serbian national assemblies.[12]^10 This petition laments the
"genocide" of the Serbian people and demands the
right to spiritual identity, to defense of the foundations of Serb
national culture and to the physical survival of our nation on its
land. We demand decisive measures, and that the concern and will of
all Yugoslavia be mobilized in order to stop the Albanian
aggression in Kosovo and Metohija.[13]^11
The petition was signed by notable intellectuals, including
former "Marxist humanist" editors of the prominent Yugoslav Marxist
journal Praxis: Zaga Golubovik, Mihailo Markovik, and Ljubomir Tadik.
The alignment of these prominent intellectuals with aggressive
nationalism not only puzzled left acolytes of Yugoslav Marxism, but
also pointed to a close connection between the latter and nationalism
that has often been elided in contemporary accounts. In a later
pronouncement on February 26, 1987, the three editors published a
rejoinder to a criticism by Michele Lee of their support of
nationalism.[14]^12 While claiming to continue to uphold the
principles of democratic socialism in the journal and the general
rights of all minorities, the three editors stress that, as Serbs,
they are also defending the "Serbian victims of oppression."[15]^13
They refer to the Albanian people as the "little David" which
always had the upper hand most of the time because it was amply
supported by overwhelming allies: the Islamic Ottoman Empire during
five centuries until 1912; Austria Hungary which occupied the
entire territory during World War I; fascist Italy and Germany
which did the same during World War II; the Soviet Union and China
after 1948; eventually a dominating anti-Serbian coalition itself
over the last twenty years.[16]^14
Notice in this description the highly relational articulation of
Serbian victimization: it emerges through the long durée of the
history of domination by foreign peoples, by enemies of all
ideological stripes and continues to this day, ostensibly embodied in
the nascent movements for autonomy taking place in other parts of
Yugoslavia. The past is always present and all the more so in the most
reflexive elements of the population, namely, the intellectuals.
These contours of Serbian history formed the central aspect of
the more general cultural milieu in which political leaders in the
disintegrating Yugoslavia existed. Serbian history really was
characterized by the series of oppressions named. What was decisive
for the fate of Bosnia was the ways in which this history was "played"
by politicians in the present. No one was a more skillful player than
Milosevic; his very power depended fundamentally on his exploitation
and intensification of these anti-Albanian sentiments and the
perception of the danger posed by Albanians to the Serbs. Indeed, what
is remarkable about the tense situation in Kosovo, both in the late
1980s and now, is the way in which the present-day Albanians are seen
as "Turk-surrogates," symbolic stand-ins for the real Turks who
defeated Prince Lazar 600 years before in 1389 at the Battle of
Kosovo. In terms of the temporal plane of history, what distinguishes
so much of the social action in the Balkans is the way in which
history resides so close to the surface, always ready to be taken into
consideration as the justification for this or that act in the
present. Milosevic set the stage for this contemporaneization of
history in a famous speech to Kosovo Polje on April 24, 1987.
Milosevic used the tensions in Kosovo to effect a transformation of
his own political identity from a communist apparatchik to nationalist
"savior of the Serbian people." This was a highly intentional act, and
while it no doubt "brewed" for some time, we have actual footage that
shows the exact moment when Milosevic recreated his identity.
The Kosovo gathering shows the volatile mix of crowd dynamics,
political calculations, the construction of charisma, and conscious
insertion of the self into history that comprise acts of agency in the
Balkans. While it is clear that Milosevic emerged victorious at this
time, what is not often commented on is the high degree of contingency
and unpredictability of this event. Like other reflexive interactions
in situations of co-presence, the interactions of a political leader
with masses is a precarious endeavor, even more so perhaps since the
reflexivity of the "masses" is not highly developed and, thus, the
leader is forced to play to the mob rather than the other way around.
Milosevic might well have emerged a villain rather than a hero, and
the contingency of the event is evident in the way the situation
played itself out. While the event was highly orchestrated, the leader
seemed ever conscious of the precariousness of the situation and only
"struck" when he was sure that the identity he had chosen would
resonate with the crowd.
Milosevic's declaration, "You will not be beaten again," is an
utterance which places him, at once, in the past, present, and future:
the reference to "again" does not refer to the immediate past of the
staged and contrived attack on Serbs outside the lecture hall just a
few moments ago, but to the long-standing beating of the Serbs by
Albanians which has occurred since 1389. The utterance itself is a
reflexive orientation to the audience which, in the present, demands
something immediate of Milosevic, and the use of the future tense
means that Milosevic has defined a vision of the future in which the
Serbs will be safe from other threats. While I would not like to make
too much out of one utterance, I would say that the pattern of
"playing" the chordal triangle of past, present, and future which is
so evident in this utterance was to establish itself as the principle
grounding for destructive acts in Bosnia.
Milosevic continued this playing of past, present, and future as
he assumed more power. On May 8, 1989, Milosevic assumed the
presidency of Yugoslavia. The next month, on June 28, again at the
very battlefield where the "Turks" had defeated the Serbs, a mass
rally of over one million people was staged. Milosevic as the
transformed Serbian nationalist leader played the key role in the
spectacle, which took place at Gazimestan, at the actual site of the
battle of Kosovo. Mass audiences were convened to greet Milosevic who,
just as Hitler had descended to Nuremberg sixty years before in an
airplane, descended to the field in a helicopter to greet the people.
This spectacle continued Milosevic's reflexive transformation of his
own identity. I want to stress this because, for the purpose of my
general argument here, history is not simply a background force that
caused the dissolution of Yugoslavia and the attendant destruction of
Bosnia: it was a force that was activated by agents to refashion their
identities and, by way of that, to alter the specific contours of the
present and future.
The consideration of Milosevic as a reflexive agent is not meant
to decide the question about whether or not Milosevic is actually
"evil" in some essential sense, although the case could be made
philosophically that he is wicked, that is, he is an individual who is
an "habitual evildoer."[17]^15 The point is that in his actions we see
a strong intersection between the reflexive remaking of Milosevic's
self and the investing of that self into a series of social actions
that had a specific effect on the present and Serbian future. If it is
the case that Milosevic's actions in the beginning of the war were the
pretext for the destruction of Bosnia, it is also the case that his
own actions enabled others who were the executors of his plans for the
forcible repression of newly independent states of the former
Yugoslavia. While Milosevic's transformation set the ball in motion,
there is a seeming inconsistency between Milosevic's rather
dispassionate and bureaucratic demeanor and the events that have come
to characterize the war in ex-Yugoslavia: the brutal rapes, the acts
of torture and mutilations, the killing of civilians and
non-combatants. It is very easy to see Machiavelli rather than
Rousseau in him.
Yet Milosevic's own transformation set in motion a general
movement away from pure Machiavellianism to a more "fragrant,"
contractual, and aestheticized version of transgression--transgression
that manifested itself almost as a kind of Durkheimian ritual of
negative solidarity. We can move from the analysis of the reflexive
self of a former communist party leader who turned nationalist for his
own benefit to the analysis of the true believers who precipitated
acts of cruelty in the name of the nation, the self-defense of the
victimized Serbian people. In such a movement, we see manifestations
of an autonomous evil, in which agents such as Milosevic are well
aware of what they are doing, and what John Kekes calls non-autonomous
evil, in which actors perpetrate evil acts, but are convinced that
what they are doing is good, righteous, or just.[18]^16 Whether
autonomous or non-autonomous, like Milosevic, these same actors played
the chordal triangle of past, present, and future as they committed
their acts of transgression.
IV
In his work Lectures on the Philosophy of World History, Hegel
noted, quite rightly, that "it is in world history that we encounter
the sum total of concrete evil." He was wrong, however, to surmise
that the ultimate design of the world has been realized and that "evil
has not been able to maintain a position of equality beside
it."[19]^17 Nowhere is the fact that we have not approached the "end
of history" more evident than in Bosnia: the postmodern world, with
its swirl of accounts, each circulating through the plethora of media
outlets and each sounding as plausible and true as the other, has
actually set the stage for the enabling of extreme behavior. The late
twentieth century became, in David Rieff's terms, the age of genocide,
a period in which we witnessed a particularly volatile reemergence of
evil that is troubling precisely because we have perhaps lost not only
the moral ability, but also the cognitive ability to recognize it or
even name it.
Social theorists such as Zygmunt Bauman and Norbert Elias have
noted, each in their different ways, that modern civilization is a
condition in which good and evil present themselves together. To the
Enlightenment minds, there was a troubling aspect to the pairing of
good and evil, for part of the "grand design" of the Enlightenment
project was that, through the march of time, the former was supposed
to displace the latter. Yet it is the very technologies that are
supposed to eradicate evil--the media, the rise of systems of mass
education, more refined and differentiated political systems--that
have also contributed to the emergence of new forms of cruelty and,
ironically, to the maskings of their painful truths. Hegel was wrong
to assume a telos of good or evil in world history; modernity is an
engine that drives good and evil and if, indeed, we live in a
postmodern era, it is an era in which new engines drive the history of
good and evil in different directions.
Barbarism lurks beneath the veneer of civility and not so much
as a foreign body, but as an integral part of the very constitution of
modernity. Its existence itself is troubling to the modern
consciousness, but even more troubling is its unpredictability: we
simply do not know when or where it will emerge. This
unpredictability, as much as the existence of evil itself, is a
constant source of consternation for the liberal mind. No one
predicted that Sarajevo would be transformed from a metaphor of human
cooperation into an abject symbol of hell on earth. Bosnia itself
became a metaphor of how far we could fall so fast, of the existence
of evil, geographically only hours away and in the media only
nanoseconds away from the comforting "good" of capitalist, liberal
democracy. The evil that supplanted the good in Bosnia was, however,
near the "surface" of present time, inchoate and unseen, waiting to be
put into play by specific agents in particular times and places who,
through their actions, make history.
Perhaps there is a new logic of evil in postmodernity. Agency
exists in a cultural context of swirling simulacra in which claims for
some kind of truth about the world seem absurd or simply naive. Agency
exists in relation to new forms of global media and information flows
that allow agents to more easily excavate history, manipulate the
present, and construct futures in new and even more creative--but not
necessarily progressive--ways. This dialectic is likely to yield new
expressions of evil that, at present, we can only imagine.
________________________
[20]^1 This essay was written before the atrocities committed in
Kosovo and the subsequent NATO war against Yugoslavia. As such, I have
not dealt with that case at length, although the general model
articulated here could be applied to interpret that case. This paper
has benefited from remarks by John Kekes, John Rodden, and William
Cain. ] [21]^2 Michael Bernstein, "Homage to the Extreme: The Shoah
and the Rhetoric of Catastrophe," The Times Literary Supplement (6
March 1996): 6. ] [22]^3 Nevitt Sanford and Craig Comstock, "Sanctions
for Evil," Sanctions for Evil: Sources of Social Destructiveness, ed.
Sanford, Comstock, and Associates (San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1973)
5. ] [23]^4 One of the key works to recognize that the character of
evil acts is to be found in the acts themselves and in subjectivity is
Jack Katz's Seductions of Crime: The Moral and Sensual Attractions of
Doing Evil (New York: Basic Books, 1988). Katz establishes the basis
for the sociology of evil when he notes that crime is not just a "fall
from grace, but an act of 'genuine experiential creativity'" (8). ]
[24]^5 Abigail Rosenthal, A Good Look at Evil (Philadelphia: Temple,
1987) 3. ] [25]^6 Neil Smelser, "Some Determinants of Destructive
Behavior," Sanctions for Evil, 16. ] [26]^7 John Kekes, "The
Reflexivity of Evil," Social Philosophy and Policy 15.1 (1998) : 217.
] [27]^8 Mustafa Emirbayer and Ann Mirsch, "What is Agency?," American
Journal of Sociology 103: 1012. ] [28]^9 Emirbayer and Mirsch, "What
is Agency?," 1012. ] [29]^10 The document is reprinted in its entirety
in Branka Magas, The Destruction of Yugoslavia: Tracking the Break-up
1980-92 (London: Verso, 1993) 49-52. ] [30]^11 Magas, The Destruction
of Yugoslavia, 51. ] [31]^12 This document is reprinted in its
entirety in Magas, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 55-61. ] [32]^13
Magas, The Destruction of Yugoslavia, 57. ] [33]^14 Magas, The
Destruction of Yugoslavia, 57. ] [34]^15 John Kekes' definition of a
wicked person is one who is ruled by his or her vices and who is an
habitual evildoer. ] [35]^16 Kekes, "The Reflexivity of Evil," 218. ]
[36]^17 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of
World History: Introduction, Reason in History (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1980) 42-43. ]
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list