[Paleopsych] Hedgehog: Jennifer L. Geddes: Evil Lost and Found
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Fri Oct 22 15:46:24 UTC 2004
Jennifer L. Geddes: Evil Lost and Found
The Hedgehog Review - Institute for Advanced Studies in Culture
http://etext.virginia.edu/etcbin/ot2www-hh?specfile=/texts/english/modeng/journals/hh.o2w&act=text&offset=678549&textreg=1&id=GedLost2-2
Delbanco, Andrew. The Death of Satan: How Americans Have Lost
the Sense of Evil. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1995.
Adams, Marilyn McCord. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God.
Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1999.
Introduction
The number of books on evil has been increasing rapidly,
especially in recent years. Choosing which ones to highlight in this
review was a challenging task, but I decided on two very different
works, each exemplifying a distinct facet of the study of evil--in
fact, the two books under consideration could hardly be more
different: One suggests that we have lost the sense of evil; the other
argues that an answer to the theological problems raised by evil can
be found. One is a book of history, narrative, and cultural analysis,
written from a secular, liberal perspective; the other a combination
of analytic philosophy and Christian theology. One focuses on how a
culture understands evil; the other on how individuals who have
suffered evil might come to understand their experiences. At issue in
one is the spiritual health of a culture; at issue in the other is the
possibility of individual belief in God in the face of evil. And yet,
despite these major differences, both books suggest that how we think
about evil is fundamental to the ways we understand our selves, our
communities, our societies, and our world.
Evil Lost: The Death of Satan
The work of this book is therefore to think historically about the
shrinking range of phenomena to which accusatory words like "evil"
and "sin" may still be applied in contemporary life, and to think
about what it means to do without them. I have written it out of
the belief that despite the shriveling of the old words and
concepts, we cannot do without some conceptual means for thinking
about the sorts of experiences that used to go under the name of
evil. (9)
In The Death of Satan: How Americans Have Lost the Sense of
Evil, Andrew Delbanco argues that "a gulf has opened up in our culture
between the visibility of evil and the intellectual resources
available for coping with it" (3). In fact, he argues, "the repertoire
of evil has never been richer. Yet never have our responses been so
weak" (3). The newspapers are full of accounts of atrocities happening
across the globe. Television offers us up-close images of far-away
wars, intimate shots of the victims of anonymous crimes, friendly
interviews with serial murderers, and talk shows that are designed to
display the worst sorts of hostilities that those who used to love one
another have grown to have. Horror movies bring large audiences to
theatres, and crime novels line bookstore shelves. We have a growing
fascination with images of evil at the same time that we find it
harder and harder to speak about evil. Our ability to think about
evil, to confront it in such a way that we take it seriously, resist
it, and work towards preventing it, is, Delbanco argues, extremely
deficient. Citing a recent book that described mass murderers, such as
Stalin and Hitler, as suffering from "streaks of disorder," Delbanco
exclaims, "Why can't we call them evil?" (4). The Death of Satan, he
tells us, is about "how this crisis of incompetence before evil came
about and how it has made itself felt in the United States" (3).
The Death of Satan traces the decline of the meaningfulness of
the term "evil" in the moral discourse of the American public, or, in
more metaphorical terms, it tells the story of Satan's death. This
"national spiritual autobiography" presents a history of the changes
in how Americans have understood evil, a history of American moral
life from "The Age of Belief" to "Modern Times." In "The Age of
Belief," Satan was a live and active figure. But, with the rise of
faith in reason, belief gave way to skepticism, at least where Satan
was concerned, such that "the devil was being reduced to something
that educated men could not believe in. This was the beginning of the
end of the devil as a meaningful symbol of evil" (64). This
skepticism, however, did not extend to Americans' understanding of
human nature: while belief in Satan's existence decreased, faith in
the goodness and unlimited potential of human nature increased. Rising
individualism transformed ambition and pride, once evils to be
resisted, into the crowning virtues of the self-sufficient individual.
The Civil War marked a turning point away from a complete loss
of the economy of good and evil. The glaring evil of slavery brought
the subject of evil to the forefront of moral discussions. Delbanco
notes that it was Lincoln "who did most to retrieve and renew the
dormant power of the symbols of good and evil that had been slipping
out of public life" (131). Rather than demonizing the South, Lincoln
suggested that the evil of slavery was something that Americans had to
confront as a national sin:
Lincoln's idea of evil was extremely demanding--as it had been
since Paul and Augustine first refined it into a theological
formulation. It required every prospective believer to come to
terms with himself, because, as Lincoln knew and said, no American
was uncontaminated by the racist history of the Republic. (134)
But this conception of evil as sin, as something in which "I" or
"we" take part, gave way to the view of evil as having to do with
others. The trauma of the Civil War left many with the belief that
"the world was run by chance" (143), not divine providence, and "in
what amounted to a new kind of paganism, the concept of evil devolved
into bad luck, and 'good luck' became the American benediction" (153).
The notion of sin was lost along with belief in providence. American
culture became one of panic and scapegoating. Evil was the other; and
the other was evil, whether he was foreign, black, un-American, or
"unfit." Delbanco argues that the connection of evil with the other is
related to the horrors of the Salem witch trials, slavery, racism, the
eugenics movement, the Holocaust, and McCarthyism.
Modern times, Delbanco suggests, have been characterized by a
loss of transcendence and providence, the increase in scapegoating and
blame, and a rising culture of irony. While scapegoating is moral
energy turned towards an evil purpose, Delbanco sees irony as
evacuating all moral energy. Both extremes lead to an inability to
grapple with the reality of evil. Delbanco is worried that American
culture simply oscillates between these two extremes. Concerning the
culture of irony, he asks:
Can irony yield any sense of evil? Is the ironist capable of making
discriminations of value? Or is he condemned to live in a
continuous world of morally indistinguishable actions and events,
in which all ideas are designated ideologies? In the face of some
new Stalin or Hitler, is it possible to shake off the lethargy
induced by irony and rise to the fight? History does not encourage
an affirmative answer to these questions...Without reverence for
something, there can be no proscriptions--and it should be clear
enough to any observer of contemporary culture that we are short on
both. Irony has proven to be a more potent solvent of our erstwhile
beliefs than any contending belief...Its energy is negative.
(210-211)
In a culture of irony, saturated with images of evil, how can we
resist evil? The preponderance of images of evil anesthetizes us to
evil, and the culture of irony evacuates any sense of responsibility
or moral urgency that such images might raise in us. If we no longer
think that there is any foundation on which to judge something evil,
how can we proscribe certain actions, much less fight against them?
And how can we affirm the good, a vision of the future towards which
to work, an understanding of good character towards which to strive,
without an understanding of what sorts of things to leave out, to
avoid, to fight against?
While Delbanco's analysis of American public culture is
accurate, it is important to note that most Americans do not live by
irony, but rather maneuver their way through the world with a moral
system informed by particular religious traditions. Delbanco tells us
that he has "left these people out of this book--because the story [he
has] tried to tell is the story of the advance of secular rationality
in the United States, which has been relentless in the face of all
resistance" (221). Delbanco's use of the word "we" is problematic.
When he suggests that "whether we welcome or mourn this loss, it is
the central and irreversible fact of modern history that we no longer
inhabit a world of transcendence" (220), he forgets that many of the
"we" (if it is really to refer to "Americans") do see themselves as
inhabiting a world of transcendence. While secular liberals
"acknowledge that no story about the intrinsic meaning of the world
has universal validity" (221), they should also acknowledge that a
large number of Americans disagree with them.
This diversity of beliefs in the United States is particularly
important to note, especially given Delbanco's identification of an
American cultural dialectic in which we seem to move between, on the
one hand, pouring out our moral energies against an evil other--a
fundamentalist demonizing that seems to characterize both sides of
contentious debates, such as those on abortion, in which each side
sees the other as evil and uses extreme rhetoric to prove it--and, on
the other hand, withdrawing into an ironic stance of non-involvement
and smug self-absorption. As Delbanco himself notes, the division
between those who believe in some sort of transcendence and those who
are committed to secular rationalism is a potential source of great
unrest in this country:
Now, at the end of the twentieth century, we are, I believe,
dividing between two sensibilities that correspond to belief and
irony. The conflict between these two sensibilities has, I believe,
more potential for rancor and ferocity than any of the preceding
oppositions. (223)
But Delbanco is hopeful that these two sides may work together
in renewing a language of evil that might serve us in our efforts to
prevent and resist it. He suggests that there "may be reason to hope
for a cooperative intellectual venture between religion and science
that may lead to a revival of serious moral thinking, in which the
category of evil might once again have meaning" (228). Just what form
this cooperative intellectual effort might take is unclear. And it is
at this point that the book's limitations are made clear.
Delbanco's book is a wonderfully written and perceptive
diagnosis of a current cultural crisis in the face of evil, but its
constructive offerings are slim. Delbanco has little to offer in the
way of solutions. Strangely enough for a self-professed secular
liberal, he suggests that we revisit the Judeo-Christian notion of sin
and the Augustinian view of evil as privation--that is, evil as an
absence, lack, distortion of the good. Delbanco admits that the idea
that "sin is finally best understood as a failure of knowledge--a
lack, an obtuseness, a poverty of imagination" (232) may seem a meager
offering, may seem "pathetically inadequate, even offensive" (232), in
the face of twentieth-century atrocities, but he thinks that such a
conception of evil resists both the temptation to demonize the other
and the temptation to withdraw from grappling with evil. When we
recognize our own potential for evil, Delbanco argues, we are less
likely to look for it in the face of others; and, conversely, when we
fail to acknowledge our own potential for evil, we leave ourselves
open to be overtaken by evil. He tells us that his
driving motive in writing [this book] has been the conviction that
if evil, with all the insidious complexity which Augustine
attributed to it, escapes the reach of our imagination, it will
have established dominion over us all. If the privative conception
of evil continues to be lost between liberal irony on the one hand,
and fundamentalist demonizing on the other, we shall have no way of
confronting the most challenging experiences of our private and
public lives. (234)
It is unclear, however, just how the view of evil as privation,
divorced from the religious traditions in which it makes sense, can
give us the ability or reason to confront a new Stalin or Hitler. And
what exactly Delbanco means here by the "reach of our imagination" is
one of the challenges of the book. What would it mean for our
imaginations to have "grasped" evil?
And yet, Delbanco himself is proof that we--even "we secular
liberals"--have not altogether lost the sense of evil. His book has a
compelling tone of moral urgency to it. He is worried about the world
his children will inherit and believes that how we think about evil is
constitutive of that world. And precisely because of its tone, the
book suggests that that the situation is, perhaps, not as dire as he
makes out.
Found: Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God
My central thesis in this book is that horrendous evils require
defeat by nothing less than the goodness of God. My strategy for
showing how this can be done is to identify the ways that created
participation in horrors can be integrated into the participants'
relation to God, where God is understood to be the incommensurate
Good, and the relation to God is one that is overall
incommensurately good for the participant. (155)
While Delbanco focuses on a general cultural trend--our waning
resources for responding to evil--Marilyn McCord Adams, in Horrendous
Evils and the Goodness of God, explores what a particular religious
tradition has to offer in response to the question: How can God be
good given that there is so much evil in the world? And while Delbanco
suggests that we need a cultural language of evil, one that can be
used by Americans in confronting the worst sorts of things that people
suffer and do to one another, Adams attempts to provide a language of
evil through recourse to the resources of the Christian faith. At
stake in Adams' book is not the ability to chart a moral landscape or
to judge the health of a society, but rather the possibility of belief
in the goodness of God in the face of evil.
Adams provides the reader with helpful summaries of the major
arguments that have been presented over the last several decades on
the problem of evil, pointing out the connections and disagreements
among them and between them and her own. For this reason alone, the
book will be very useful to anyone interested in philosophical
discussions of the problem of evil. Her own argument is rich in detail
and multi-stranded; it draws deeply on the resources offered by
numerous areas of study, including philosophy, theology, anthropology,
and psychology. This is due in part to her belief that it is not
possible to find one morally sufficient reason as to why God permits
evil; only partial reasons can be found, but together these partial
reasons give sufficient evidence to show that belief in the goodness
of God is not irrational.
Adams describes herself as writing in the two traditions of the
philosophy of religion and Christian philosophy, and her book displays
the virtues and limitations of each. The book's attention to detail
and conceptual clarity, characteristic of analytic philosophy, make it
challenging and provocative, though its prose style can be, at times,
tedious. It provides Christians with both rich resources for
responding to the problem of evil and a provocative theology of the
afterlife; however, the argument is based on assumptions that those
who are not Christians do not believe, limiting the usefulness such an
argument has for those outside the Christian faith.
Adams suggests that there are three major problems with current
philosophical discussions of evil, all having to do with their high
level of abstraction. First, these discussions consider evil in
general--the mere fact of evil--rather than particular sorts of evil,
especially the worst sorts of evil. Adams suggests that "our
philosophical propensity for generic solutions--our search for a
single explanation that would cover all evils at once--has permitted
us to ignore the worst sorts of evil in particular" (3). The second
problem, a corollary to the first, is that these discussions fail to
confront the problem of evil in individuals' lives and instead deal
with evil as a global concern. Furthermore, they seek either to
disprove or prove the existence of a generic god, rather than a
particular god believed in by followers of a particular religious
tradition. Referring to J. L. Mackie, who worked out some of the
strongest arguments against belief in God, Adams notes that
it would be a hollow victory for the believer to stop with showing
that the God that Mackie doesn't believe in (essentially
omniscient, omnipotent, and perfectly good in Mackie's sense) could
coexist with evils, if that God is not the one the believer
confesses. (13)
A fourth problem Adams finds in most philosophical discussions
of evil is their failure adequately to take into account just how vast
the difference is between Divine and human agency, and thereby, to
understand properly the relationship between humans and God and
between evils and the goodness of God.
In contrast to these abstractions in relation to the kind and
scope of evil and the nature of God, and in contrast to the
misconstrual of Divine agency, Adams proposes to show how one might
believe in the goodness of the Christian God given the "horrendous
evils" that happen to individuals. By "horrendous evils" Adams means
evils the participation in which (that is, the doing and the
suffering) constitutes prima facie reason to doubt whether the
participant's life could (given their inclusion in it) be a great
good to him/her on the whole. The class of paradigm horrors
includes both individual and massive collective
suffering...examples include the rape of a woman and axing off of
her arms, psycho-physical torture whose ultimate goal is the
disintegration of personality, betrayal of one's deepest loyalties,
child abuse of the sort described by Ivan Karamazov, child
pornography, parental incest, slow death by starvation, the
explosion of nuclear bombs over populated areas. (26)
Adams argues that the goodness of God must be something that the
very individuals who suffer these horrendous evils can affirm,
something that they themselves experience. She does not argue that in
the end the good of eternity will outweigh all the evils that have
occurred in the world--a sort of happy mathematics in which the
positive outweighs the negative. Global-good-over-global-evil
arguments are open to the charge that they justify the suffering of
some people for the benefit of others and justify the sacrifice of
some people for the sake of others. Instead, Adams argues that after
death, or "post-mortem," to use Adams' phrase, each individual,
including the very individuals on whom the worst evils have been
inflicted, will come to see his or her suffering "defeated" by the
goodness of God.
Exactly what Adams means when she suggests that evil will be
"defeated" is hard to figure out. She means at least that God will
restore and heal the broken person and that the individual will come
to see a positive aspect to his or her suffering. God renarrates an
individual's life story such that he or she can see the evil suffered
as part of a good whole. Adams suggests that it is
straightforward to credit God with [the] superlative imagination
needed to make sense of horrors that stump us, and to think of the
meaning-making God as also the Teacher Who coaches us to recognize
and appropriate objective meanings already (Divinely) given, Who
heals and helps us to make new meanings ourselves. (82)
Adams proposes that we think of the relationship of God to
humans as that like a mother to her infant: the difference in agency
is just as vast, and the abilities of the individual to comprehend his
own actions or his environment, when considered in relation to God's,
are just as limited as a baby's are in relation to its mother. The
goodness of God is so good, so beyond our possibility to quantify
goodness, that it can outweigh and "defeat" evil.
Adams' argument is extremely complex and nuanced--this short
review cannot begin even to chart an outline of it, but can only
highlight its main thrust--but there is one element of it that is
glaringly troublesome: Adams erases the difference between
perpetrators and victims of evil. According to Adams, both the child
who was raped and the adult who raped her come to see a positive
aspect to their participation in evil, both experience the goodness of
God in such a way as to "defeat" their participation in evil, and both
see their participation in evil as part of the good unity of their
lives. Here the word "participation" serves a sinister purpose, in
that it erases and ignores the difference between inflicting evil and
suffering evil. Adams tells us that "the morally innocent participate
in horrors both as victims and as perpetrators" (125). The problem
with this statement is that unless the term "morally innocent" is a
meaningless phrase (in which case it should not be used at all), it
cannot be ascribed to perpetrators of horrors. Adams' mother-infant
analogy reflects her sense that the evils that seem so horrifying to
us here will post-mortem come to be seen, in the light of God's great
goodness, as a child's mistake. A god who rewrites the history of an
individual's life such that his active torture of a child is
understood to be the foolish mistake of a vulnerable, immature human,
is a god who, at least according to this reader, does not care about
justice.
Though I think it falters on its absorption of the demands of
justice into a therapeutic logic of post-mortem healing, Adams'
argument is an important contribution to recent philosophical and
theological discussions on the problem of evil. Her suggestions that
specific evils (and the worst kinds of evils) be considered, that the
value of each individual life not be overlooked, that the god under
consideration be one that is not the construction of philosophy but
one in which individuals actually believe, that anthropomorphizing
tendencies be resisted when discussing at least the Christian God--all
of these are welcome corrections to discussions of generic evils and a
generic god.
Conclusion
Though they have written extremely different books, Adams and
Delbanco both grapple with the grip that evil has over our
lives--whether it causes us to question our belief in God or leads us
to oscillate between finding scapegoats, on the one hand, and ignoring
the suffering and injustices around us, on the other. Both suggest
that resisting evil involves careful and sustained thought, and both
are themselves role models in such an endeavor. Evil is not something
that we will "figure out," but it is certainly something that we must
be continually in the process of preventing, confronting, and
resisting. Whether one agrees with Delbanco's cultural diagnosis or
embraces Adams' answer to the problem of evil, it is hard not to think
that we are better off for the ways that their attempts to think about
evil encourage and challenge us to take evil seriously.
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list