[Paleopsych] Hedgehog: John Steadman Rice: Romantic Modernism and the Self
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Mon Oct 25 14:48:27 UTC 2004
John Steadman Rice: Romantic Modernism and the Self
The Hedgehog Review - Institute for Advanced Studies in Culture
http://etext.virginia.edu/etcbin/ot2www-hh?specfile=/texts/english/modeng/journals/hh.o2w&act=text&offset=1152442&textreg=1&id=RicRoma1-1
Conceptualizations of the self have been central to postmodern
thought, but, John Rice asks, from what sources do these
conceptualizations draw? In an historical analysis, he traces the
roots of postmodern theorizing to one strain, the romantic strain, of
modernist critique. While Romantic Modernism has a long history, it
was only with its incarnation in the human potential movement after
mid-century that it began its ascent to victory over another strain of
modernist critique, what Rice calls "social scientific modernism." The
triumph of Romantic Modernism, he argues, has come in the form of the
growing cultural authority of a therapeutic ethic, and it is this
selfsame ethic that informs much postmodern thinking about the self.
Rice explores the Romantic Modernist view of the self and early
attempts to institutionalize it. Especially concerned with the
relationship between the individual and his or her community, he
discusses the various ways by which the Romantic self attempts to
assert its authority over society.
John Steadman Rice teaches in the Watson School of Education at
the University of North Carolina, Wilmington. He is the author of A
Disease of One's Own: Psychotherapy, Addiction, and the Emergence of
Co-Dependency, and a forthcoming book on the institutionalization of
therapeutic culture.
Romantic modernism espouses and rests upon a distinction between
formal rationality and emotion, intuition, spirituality, and
individual expressive freedom. This distinction is reflected in the
Romantic Modernist view of the appropriate relationship between the
individual and society, which is predicated upon a distinction between
a true self and a false self, with the latter understood in terms of
the social roles that society imposes upon and demands of the
individual. This societal imposition, in turn, is seen as a violation
of the self's integrity and the individual's expressive freedom.
Indeed, a "feeling of being violated by an inimical society...lies at
the root of Romantic alienation,"[3]^1 an alienation born of the
Romantic Modernist's apprehensive "consciousness of the void beneath
the conventional structures of reality."[4]^2
This premise of the self's violation at the hands of an
"inimical society," however, is but the dark side of the Romantic
Modernist world view. This "negative Romanticism" is perhaps most
clearly embodied in American literature by the work of Edgar Allan
Poe, whose oeuvre repeatedly emphasizes the horrors of the
age--horrors, in turn, that resonate with the Romantic Modernist
convictions that rationalism is bankrupt and that the modern self is
doomed to estrangement, isolation, alienation, madness, and so on. Nor
are these uniquely American strains of Romanticism. Indeed, Mary
Shelley's Frankenstein is also a Romantic allegory as to the
consequences of modernity's heedless reliance on scientific versions
of rationalism.
Romantic Modernism, however, is not solely focused on or
oriented by this negative view. In contrast both to rationalism and
its bleak consequences, another theme in Romantic Modernism posits the
self as the source of value in the world. As such, the dedicated
(Romantic) individual bears special burdens and is presented with
special opportunities as well: "a Romantic figure was first of all
faced with discovering a way to project his will upon the external
world in order to reassert the dominance of human value and thereby
his own identity."[5]^3
This more positive strand of Romanticism is most clearly
embodied in the American Transcendentalist movement of the early
nineteenth century.[6]^4 Sharing in negative Romanticism's dark
assessment of the emerging social structures of bureaucratic
industrialism, "the principal cause of human failure seemed obvious to
[the Transcendentalists]: it was society, that mass of forms and
conventions and institutions by which men were held captive, alienated
from their true selves."[7]^5 Indeed, "for a Transcendentalist all
social structures can become oppressive institutions...that perpetuate
themselves by restricting moral choice."[8]^6
The assumption that conventional society and culture obstruct
the self's natural development is coupled, in Romantic Modernism, with
the assumption that humans contain within themselves all of the
requisite capacities and impulses needed to construct and maintain a
just and equitable social order. The Transcendentalists, for example,
maintained that humans possess, by nature, a divine inner being, an
innate and benevolent spirituality. As such, individuals must be free
to develop these innate capacities through "a process of growth,
unfolding and ripening, a gradual realization of inherent qualities
latent in the organism from its very birth"--a process, again,
believed to be "thwarted in its development by a...conformist
society."[9]^7
These assumptions about human nature, and about the relationship
between the individual and society, express a profoundly
anti-institutional orientation. That orientation, moreover, translates
into a clear course of action in which the self's expressive and
experiential freedom receives ultimate priority over conventional
social expectations. Thus, the Transcendentalists called for "the
liberation of [hu]mankind, the release of a power everywhere latent
but everywhere suppressed or unawakened."[10]^8 The assertion of the
individual's will--the projection, as noted above, of that will onto
the external world--was, of course, an abiding theme in
Transcendentalist essays and poetry. Thoreau, for one, repeatedly
stressed precisely this theme. For example, in Civil Disobedience, he
baldly asserts that "the only obligation which I have a right to
assume is to do at any time what I think is right."[11]^9 Emerson
espoused precisely the same point even more succinctly: "The
individual is the world."[12]^10
One mechanism for cultivating and releasing the individual's
latent powers was expressed in Emanuel Swedenborg's concept of
"correspondence," especially as that idea was interpreted and
articulated by Swedenborg's student, Sampson Reed. Emerson, in
particular, was much taken with Reed's Observations on the Growth of
Mind, which, following Swedenborg, asserts that the basic endowments
of self, when carefully and meticulously cultivated, correspond with a
realm of divine truth. Reflecting this presumed equivalency between
the divine and our true human nature, the moment at which
correspondence ostensibly occurs is called "the experience of
`self-remembering,'" an experience in which "the perceiver not only
records his perceptions but also experiences himself in the act of
perception."[13]^11
For the Transcendentalists, correspondence could be realized in
and through exposure to and contemplation of the divine truths of
nature--a theme that plainly infused, for example, Thoreau's Walden,
and that was also expressed in Emerson's famous "transparent eyeball,"
featured in the essay, "The Oversoul":
Standing on the bare ground--my head bathed by the blithe air, and
uplifted into infinite space--all mean egotism vanishes. I become a
transparent eyeball. I am nothing. I see all. The currents of the
Universal Being circulate through me; I am part or particle of
God.[14]^12
The Romantic Modernists' convictions regarding the divine
essence of humankind were the basis for their antipathy toward social
conventions and institutions. Conventional social structures merely
sought to bring people into line with standards external to the self,
rather than operating in ways that would facilitate the individual's
"natural" process of development. Summarizing the inherent conflict
between self and conventional society built into this convergence of
convictions, Elizabeth Peabody contended that, "if there is a divine
principle in man, it has a right, and it is its duty to unfold itself
from itself. . . A social organization, which does not admit of this,
which does not favor, and cherish, and act with main reference to
promoting it, is inadequate, false, devilish."[15]^13 In addition to
concisely expressing Transcendentalism's view of human nature,
Peabody's remarks regarding social organization also underscored a key
challenge for Romantic Modernists: to devise institutions which
facilitated rather than thwarted self-cultivation.
This effort to institutionalize Romantic Modernism was plainly
the impetus for Bronson Alcott's experiments with alternative
education. In his journal of 1828, Alcott outlined some key tenets of
Transcendentalist educational philosophy, all of which resonate with
the presumptions underlying the Romantic Modernist world view. For
example, reflecting that world view's assumption that human talents
and capacities are present from birth, Alcott believed that it was
counter-productive to require children to learn, master, and remember
lessons gleaned from books: instead, the instructor "should look to
the child to see what is to be done. . . .The child is the
book."[16]^14 Further reflecting his impatience with the view of
education as a matter of imparting--and imposing, really--standardized
knowledge to students, and then evaluating them as to the degree that
they demonstrate understanding and mastery of that knowledge, Alcott
maintained that the appropriate approach to education was to "let [the
instructor] follow out the impulses, the thoughts, the volitions of
the child's mind and heart."[17]^15 As George Hochfield notes, with
this approach:
The focus is shifted from subject matter or social outcome to the
child as an end in himself; the inner world takes priority over the
outer; and the teacher's function is to stimulate the independent
growth of his pupil rather than force upon him an extraneous burden
of learning.[18]^16
Ultimately, Alcott's alternative school failed to survive, as
have other attempts to transmute Romantic Modernism into enduring
social form. The key point here, and one to which we will necessarily
return, is that such failures reflect just how inordinately difficult
it is to institutionalize a fundamentally anti-institutional world
view--a point the Transcendentalists also learned in their
unsuccessful attempt to construct an alternative society oriented
around their shared premises. That attempt, of course, was the
short-lived (1841-1847) Brook Farm Institute of Agriculture and
Education.[19]^17 Brook Farm was to be an economically self-sufficient
community, which, at the same time and more fundamentally, was also to
serve as a context in which each member could pursue his or her own
self-cultivation. The combination of these goals was reflected in,
among other things, the original charter's stipulation that each
person's contribution to the labors of the Farm was to be strictly on
a voluntary basis (a provision which--not incidentally--proved hugely
unsuccessful, as volunteers were few and irregular in their
commitments). Ultimately, and despite the introduction of Fourierist
principles in an attempt to salvage the Farm after the first three
singularly unsuccessful years, Brook Farm failed, and the community
disbanded.
Brook Farm's demise again illustrates the point with which we
are concerned, as its failure was primarily the product of the
anti-institutional premises upon which it was based. Because of the
Romantic Modernist's understanding of the relationship between self
and society, the principal shared value among the Brook Farmers was
that the self must not submit to group constraints. As such, although
the Transcendentalists "may have had some sort of vague admiration for
the vision of a cooperative community,...when it came to cooperating
in fact, the members [of Brook Farm] tended to be excessively tender
about compromising the integrity of their personalities."[20]^18 This
"tenderness," this unwillingness to submit to the expectations of
others, issued from and reflected the core convictions of Romantic
Modernism itself. Indeed, "the transcendental virtues...militated
against [Brook Farm's] success,"[21]^19 and those virtues were
Romantic Modernist in nature.
________________________
[22]^1 Michael J. Hoffman, The Subversive Vision: American Romanticism
in Literature (Port Washington, NY: Kennikat, 1972) 46. ] [23]^2
Hoffman 9. ] [24]^3 Hoffman 11. Rather than clutter up the text with
excessive uses of "sic," it seems more appropriate to simply point out
that a number of the sources for this article antedate sensitivity to
gender in language. ] [25]^4 The literature on Romanticism and
Transcendentalism is, of course, voluminous. In addition to those
cited, I have found the following to be especially insightful and
informative: Morse Peckham, "Towards a Theory of Romanticism: II.
Reconsiderations," Studies in Romanticism I (Autumn, 1961): 1-8;
Peckham, Beyond the Tragic Vision: The Quest for Identity in the
Nineteenth Century (New York: Braziller, 1962); Peckham, Romanticism:
The Culture of the Nineteenth Century (New York: Braziller, 1965);
Peckham, The Triumph of Romanticism: Collected Essays (Columbia, SC:
University of South Carolina Press, 1970); Catherine Albanese,
Introduction, The Spirituality of the American Transcendentalists:
Selected Writings of Ralph Waldo Emerson, Amos Bronson Alcott,
Theodore Parker, and Henry David Thoreau, ed. Albanese (Macon, GA:
Mercer University Press, 1988) 1-28; Arthur E. Christy, The Orient in
American Transcendentalism: A Study of Emerson, Thoreau, and Alcott
(1932; New York: Octagon, 1978); Perry Miller, ed., The American
Transcendentalists: Their Prose and Poetry (Garden City, NY:
Doubleday, 1957); Francis O. Mathiessen, American Renaissance: Art and
Expression in the Age of Emerson and Whitman (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1941); Philip F. Gura and Joel Myerson, eds.,
Critical Essays on American Transcendentalism (Boston: G.K. Hall,
1982). For an excellent and explicitly sociological analysis of
Transcendentalism, see Anne C. Rose, Transcendentalism as a Social
Movement 1830-1850 (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981). ] [26]^5
George Hochfield, "New England Transcendentalism," Critical Essays on
American Transcendentalism, ed. Philip F. Gura and Joel Myerson
(Boston: G.K. Hall, 1982) 461. ] [27]^6 Hoffman 50, 54. ] [28]^7
Hochfield 462. ] [29]^8 Hochfield 461. ] [30]^9 Henry David Thoreau as
quoted in Hochfield 477. ] [31]^10 Ralph Waldo Emerson, "Historic
Notes of Life and Letters in New England," The American
Transcendentalists: Their Prose and Poetry, ed. Perry Miller (Garden
City, NY: Doubleday, 1957) 5. ] [32]^11 Elizabeth A. Meese,
paraphrasing Robert S. De Ropp, "Transcendentalism: The Metaphysics of
the Theme," Critical Essays on American Transcendentalism, ed. Philip
F. Gura and Joel Myerson (Boston: G.K. Hall, 1982) 514. ] [33]^12
Ralph Waldo Emerson, "The Oversoul," The Collected Works of Ralph
Waldo Emerson, vol. 1, ed. Alfred R. Ferguson (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1971) 10. ] [34]^13 Elizabeth Peabody, "A Glimpse of
Christ's Idea of Society," The Dial 2 (October, 1841): 499. ] [35]^14
Hochfield 464. ] [36]^15 Bronson Alcott as quoted in Hochfield 464. ]
[37]^16 Hochfield 465 (emphasis mine). ] [38]^17 The discussion of
Brook Farm draws upon Rose's excellent monograph Transcendentalism as
a Social Movement 1830-1850. ] [39]^18 Duane E. Smith, "Romanticism in
America: The Transcendentalists," Critical Essays on American
Transcendentalism, ed. Philip F. Gura and Joel Myerson (Boston: G.K.
Hall, 1982) 497. ] [40]^19 Smith 497. ]
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list