[Paleopsych] LRB: Slavoj Zizek: The Two Totalitarianisms
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Sun Apr 17 16:46:32 UTC 2005
Slavoj Zizek: The Two Totalitarianisms
http://www.lrb.co.uk/v27/n06/print/zize01_.html
London Review of Books
Vol. 27 No. 6 dated 17 March 2005
A small note - not the stuff of headlines, obviously - appeared in the
newspapers on 3 February. In response to a call for the prohibition of
the public display of the swastika and other Nazi symbols, a group of
conservative members of the European Parliament, mostly from
ex-Communist countries, demanded that the same apply to Communist
symbols: not only the hammer and sickle, but even the red star. This
proposal should not be dismissed lightly: it suggests a deep change in
Europe's ideological identity.
Till now, to put it straightforwardly, Stalinism hasn't been rejected
in the same way as Nazism. We are fully aware of its monstrous
aspects, but still find Ostalgie acceptable: you can make Goodbye
Lenin!, but Goodbye Hitler! is unthinkable. Why? To take another
example: in Germany, many CDs featuring old East German Revolutionary
and Party songs, from `Stalin, Freund, Genosse' to `Die Partei hat
immer Recht', are easy to find. You would have to look rather harder
for a collection of Nazi songs. Even at this anecdotal level, the
difference between the Nazi and Stalinist universes is clear, just as
it is when we recall that in the Stalinist show trials, the accused
had publicly to confess his crimes and give an account of how he came
to commit them, whereas the Nazis would never have required a Jew to
confess that he was involved in a Jewish plot against the German
nation. The reason is clear. Stalinism conceived itself as part of the
Enlightenment tradition, according to which, truth being accessible to
any rational man, no matter how depraved, everyone must be regarded as
responsible for his crimes. But for the Nazis the guilt of the Jews
was a fact of their biological constitution: there was no need to
prove they were guilty, since they were guilty by virtue of being
Jews.
In the Stalinist ideological imaginary, universal reason is
objectivised in the guise of the inexorable laws of historical
progress, and we are all its servants, the leader included. A Nazi
leader, having delivered a speech, stood and silently accepted the
applause, but under Stalinism, when the obligatory applause exploded
at the end of the leader's speech, he stood up and joined in. In Ernst
Lubitsch's To Be or Not to Be, Hitler responds to the Nazi salute by
raising his hand and saying: `Heil myself!' This is pure humour
because it could never have happened in reality, while Stalin
effectively did `hail himself' when he joined others in the applause.
Consider the fact that, on Stalin's birthday, prisoners would send him
congratulatory telegrams from the darkest gulags: it isn't possible to
imagine a Jew in Auschwitz sending Hitler such a telegram. It is a
tasteless distinction, but it supports the contention that under
Stalin, the ruling ideology presupposed a space in which the leader
and his subjects could meet as servants of Historical Reason. Under
Stalin, all people were, theoretically, equal.
We do not find in Nazism any equivalent to the dissident Communists
who risked their lives fighting what they perceived as the
`bureaucratic deformation' of socialism in the USSR and its empire:
there was no one in Nazi Germany who advocated `Nazism with a human
face'. Herein lies the flaw (and the bias) of all attempts, such as
that of the conservative historian Ernst Nolte, to adopt a neutral
position - i.e. to ask why we don't apply the same standards to the
Communists as we apply to the Nazis. If Heidegger cannot be pardoned
for his flirtation with Nazism, why can Lukács and Brecht and others
be pardoned for their much longer engagement with Stalinism? This
position reduces Nazism to a reaction to, and repetition of, practices
already found in Bolshevism - terror, concentration camps, the
struggle to the death against political enemies - so that the
`original sin' is that of Communism.
In the late 1980s, Nolte was Habermas's principal opponent in the
so-called Revisionismusstreit, arguing that Nazism should not be
regarded as the incomparable evil of the 20th century. Not only did
Nazism, reprehensible as it was, appear after Communism: it was an
excessive reaction to the Communist threat, and all its horrors were
merely copies of those already perpetrated under Soviet Communism.
Nolte's idea is that Communism and Nazism share the same totalitarian
form, and the difference between them consists only in the difference
between the empirical agents which fill their respective structural
roles (`Jews' instead of `class enemy'). The usual liberal reaction to
Nolte is that he relativises Nazism, reducing it to a secondary echo
of the Communist evil. However, even if we leave aside the unhelpful
comparison between Communism - a thwarted attempt at liberation - and
the radical evil of Nazism, we should still concede Nolte's central
point. Nazism was effectively a reaction to the Communist threat; it
did effectively replace class struggle with the struggle between
Aryans and Jews. What we are dealing with here is displacement in the
Freudian sense of the term (Verschiebung): Nazism displaces class
struggle onto racial struggle and in doing so obfuscates its true
nature. What changes in the passage from Communism to Nazism is a
matter of form, and it is in this that the Nazi ideological
mystification resides: the political struggle is naturalised as racial
conflict, the class antagonism inherent in the social structure
reduced to the invasion of a foreign (Jewish) body which disturbs the
harmony of the Aryan community. It is not, as Nolte claims, that there
is in both cases the same formal antagonistic structure, but that the
place of the enemy is filled by a different element (class, race).
Class antagonism, unlike racial difference and conflict, is absolutely
inherent to and constitutive of the social field; Fascism displaces
this essential antagonism.
It's appropriate, then, to recognise the tragedy of the October
Revolution: both its unique emancipatory potential and the historical
necessity of its Stalinist outcome. We should have the honesty to
acknowledge that the Stalinist purges were in a way more `irrational'
than the Fascist violence: its excess is an unmistakable sign that, in
contrast to Fascism, Stalinism was a case of an authentic revolution
perverted. Under Fascism, even in Nazi Germany, it was possible to
survive, to maintain the appearance of a `normal' everyday life, if
one did not involve oneself in any oppositional political activity
(and, of course, if one were not Jewish). Under Stalin in the late
1930s, on the other hand, nobody was safe: anyone could be
unexpectedly denounced, arrested and shot as a traitor. The
irrationality of Nazism was `condensed' in anti-semitism - in its
belief in the Jewish plot - while the irrationality of Stalinism
pervaded the entire social body. For that reason, Nazi police
investigators looked for proofs and traces of active opposition to the
regime, whereas Stalin's investigators were happy to fabricate
evidence, invent plots etc.
We should also admit that we still lack a satisfactory theory of
Stalinism. It is, in this respect, a scandal that the Frankfurt School
failed to produce a systematic and thorough analysis of the
phenomenon. The exceptions are telling: Franz Neumann's Behemoth
(1942), which suggested that the three great world-systems - New Deal
capitalism, Fascism and Stalinism - tended towards the same
bureaucratic, globally organised, `administered' society; Herbert
Marcuse's Soviet Marxism (1958), his least passionate book, a
strangely neutral analysis of Soviet ideology with no clear
commitments; and, finally, in the 1980s, the attempts by some
Habermasians who, reflecting on the emerging dissident phenomena,
endeavoured to elaborate the notion of civil society as a site of
resistance to the Communist regime - interesting, but not a global
theory of the specificity of Stalinist totalitarianism. How could a
school of Marxist thought that claimed to focus on the conditions of
the failure of the emancipatory project abstain from analysing the
nightmare of `actually existing socialism'? And was its focus on
Fascism not a silent admission of the failure to confront the real
trauma?
It is here that one has to make a choice. The `pure' liberal attitude
towards Leftist and Rightist `totalitarianism' - that they are both
bad, based on the intolerance of political and other differences, the
rejection of democratic and humanist values etc - is a priori false.
It is necessary to take sides and proclaim Fascism fundamentally
`worse' than Communism. The alternative, the notion that it is even
possible to compare rationally the two totalitarianisms, tends to
produce the conclusion - explicit or implicit - that Fascism was the
lesser evil, an understandable reaction to the Communist threat. When,
in September 2003, Silvio Berlusconi provoked a violent outcry with
his observation that Mussolini, unlike Hitler, Stalin or Saddam
Hussein, never killed anyone, the true scandal was that, far from
being an expression of Berlusconi's idiosyncrasy, his statement was
part of an ongoing project to change the terms of a postwar European
identity hitherto based on anti-Fascist unity. That is the proper
context in which to understand the European conservatives' call for
the prohibition of Communist symbols.
[14]Slavoj Zizek, a psychoanalyst and dialectical materialist
philosopher, is a senior researcher at the University of Ljubljana and
international co-director of the Centre for Humanities at Birkbeck
College in London.
References
14. http://www.lrb.co.uk/contribhome.php?get=zize01
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list