[Paleopsych] City Journal: Stanley Kurtz: Can We Make Boys and Girls Alike?
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Mon Apr 18 17:31:25 UTC 2005
Stanley Kurtz: Can We Make Boys and Girls Alike?
http://www.city-journal.org/html/15_2_boys_girls.html
2005 Spring
When Lawrence Summers suggested that biology might be partially
responsible for the relative rarity of female mathematics professors,
he was provoking an academic giant. Powerful as the president of
Harvard may be, his influence is as nothing compared with that of the
behemoth that is the women's studies movement. The field of women's
studies originated in the heady sixties and grew exponentially through
the seventies and eighties. By the mid-nineties, when Daphne Patai and
Noretta Koertge published Professing Feminism, their searing critique
of the field, more than 600 undergraduate and several dozen graduate
women's studies programs were up and running at colleges and
universities across the country.
The intellectual cornerstone of women's studies is "gender," the
notion that differences between men and women are not rooted in
biology, as Summers had hypothesized some might be, but are cultural
artifacts, inculcated by an oppressive patriarchal society. Precisely
because the gender idea builds a specific (radical) political
orientation into the field, Patai and Koertge point out, women's
studies proved intellectually suspect from the start. You can read
that radical politics right in the National Women's Studies
Association constitution: "Women's Studies . . . is equipping women to
transform the world to one that will be free of all oppression . . .
[and is] a force which furthers the realization of feminist aims."
True justice for these radical feminists means overcoming gender and
establishing an androgynous society. So when Summers asserted that
something besides artificial cultural roles--something besides
"gender"--might account for the distinct positions of men and women in
society, he was undermining the intellectual and political foundation
of the entire women's studies establishment.
The alternatives to feminist orthodoxy don't end with Summers-style
invocations of biology as destiny. Take psychiatrist Leonard Sax's new
book, Why Gender Matters: What Parents and Teachers Need to Know About
the Emerging Science of Sex Differences, for example. Sax begins by
arguing that variations in how boys and girls learn result from brain
biology. But, unlike many believers in hardwired sex differences, he
goes on to argue that we can triumph over biology through single-sex
education. If we teach boys and girls separately and in sync with
their biologically based learning styles, he claims, they will perform
equally well in all academics, including math.
There's also a fourth possible view on the relations between sex and
success--one that no one has systematically articulated to date. If
those who assert biological differences between the sexes disagree
about whether we can overcome them, the same might apply to those who
assert the power of cultural differences. Even if we do provisionally
hold that virtually all differences between men and women are
cultural, might it not also be true that those differences are
impossible to overcome? If so, it wouldn't be "gender" but the
feminist effort to eliminate it that is truly oppressive. This fourth
view suggests that the very same cultural forces that make feminists
desire androgyny may actually prevent us from achieving it. The
cultural sources of "gender" difference, properly understood, would
then inform us not that our gender identities are infinitely malleable
but that they're effectively impossible to change.
Sociologists have thought long and hard about the cultural
"reproduction of society"--the transmission of deeply held cultural
attitudes across the generations. Some social thinkers focus on the
conscious transmission of cultural messages through religion and
custom, while others highlight the influence of deeper social
structures, such as economic organization or family forms. The most
sophisticated feminist theories of gender--those that offer the most
plausible alternatives to biological explanations--take the latter
view. To explain the reproduction of gender differences, they zero in
on family structure, especially during the first months and years of
life, to a time when the way we care for children is far more
important than the words we speak.
A case in point is the work of psychoanalytic sociologist Nancy
Chodorow, a women's studies pioneer who gives flesh to a radically
"cultural constructivist" idea of gender. Nearly every feminist plan
for engineering a new, androgynous society--from the "egalitarian
feminism" of political theorist Susan Okin to the "difference
feminism" of developmental psychologist Carol Gilligan--offers a
variation on Chodorow's themes, so it's worth considering them
closely.
Chodorow hypothesizes that the differences between the sexes simply
derive from the contingent circumstance that women happen to be the
primary caretakers of children. The special, "feminine" empathy
required for rearing children, she suggests, becomes indelibly
associated in our minds with people who just physically happen to be
female. Identifying with their daughters, moreover, mothers tend to
stay tightly connected with them for years, drawing them into a circle
of mutual dependence and empathy that is the essence of femininity. So
it's not television ads or Barbie dolls that turn little girls into
caring women, who themselves want to be mothers. It's the emotional
closeness of mothers and daughters that perpetuates the conventional
female sexual role for generation after generation.
Boys learn their gender lessons early, too, Chodorow maintains. Since
traditional mothers assume that boys are different from girls, early
on they tend to encourage their sons to be independent. As mothers
begin to push their sons out of the warm circle of empathy, boys get
the message that people with Daddy's kind of body should act
differently from the way Mommy acts. If they want to be men, boys
learn, they've got to overcome the qualities of emotional empathy of
people like Mom. Masculinity thus finds its ground in a rejection of
"feminine" qualities.
If we could just break the association between gender and child care,
thinks Chodorow--if men as well as women could "mother" children--then
we might vanquish gender. Men and women would still have a few
distinct body parts, of course, but "masculine" and "feminine"
personality differences would no longer have anything to do with
bodily equipment. No one would assume that only people with a certain
kind of body should be caring and empathic. The speed with which a
child became independent would no longer depend on whether it was male
or female. A new era would dawn.
Yet even if this understanding of gender as learned behavior is right,
androgyny proponents quickly run into a problem. As Chodorow herself
underscores, mothering by women produces women who themselves want to
be mothers. The mechanism at work may be social and psychological,
rather than biological, but it's no less real for that. How, then, do
you get women to mother less and men to mother more, especially when,
according to Chodorow, everything in a typical male's early rearing
makes him wrong for the job?
Plato faced this dilemma when he drew up history's first great plan
for a perfectly just society in the Republic--a society that required,
among other things, androgyny. His solution: send the members of the
old, imperfect city into exile, so that the new, just city could be
built from scratch. Otherwise, their recalcitrant mental habits would
sabotage the creation of the new order. The fact is, attempts to force
a society out of its most deeply held cultural values can be every bit
as tyrannical as schemes to override our biological nature.
But what if a society actually existed--not just a theoretical
utopia--whose inhabitants yearned for androgyny? What if a society
existed whose citizens, motivated by a burning passion for perfect
justice, committed themselves to a total reorganization of the
traditional family system, with the express purpose of eliminating
gender? Such a society has existed, of course: the early Israeli
kibbutz movement. The movement wasn't just a precursor to modern
feminism, it's important to add. The kibbutzniks were utopian
socialists who wanted to construct a society where the ideal of "from
each according to his ability, to each according to his needs" would
govern the production and distribution of goods. It was as part of
this larger socialist vision that the kibbutzniks set out to wipe away
gender.
Kibbutz parents agreed to see their own children only two hours a day,
and for the remaining 22 hours to surrender them to the collective,
which would raise them androgynously (trying more to "masculinize"
women than "feminize" men). Boys and girls would henceforth do the
same kind of work and wear the same kind of clothes. Girls would learn
to be soldiers, just like boys. Signs of "bourgeois"
femininity--makeup, say--would now be taboo. As if they had stepped
out of Plato's Republic, the children would dress and undress together
and even use the same showers.
The experiment collapsed within a generation, and a traditional family
and gender system reasserted itself. Why? Those who believe in
hardwired natural differences obviously would say that cultural
conditioning couldn't remove the sexes' genetic programming. Indeed,
in his now-infamous conference remarks, Lawrence Summers invoked the
history of the kibbutz movement to help make his case that biology
might partially explain sex roles.
Feminists, though, say that the kibbutz experiment didn't get a fair
chance. However committed to gender justice the kibbutzniks might have
been, they were all traditional Europeans by upbringing. Somehow they
must have transmitted the old cultural messages about gender to the
children. Perhaps, too, those messages came from the larger Israeli
society, from which it was impossible to shelter the boys and girls
entirely. What's more--and Chodorow would doubtless emphasize this
fact--the kibbutz child-care nurses were all women. A 50/50
male-female mix might have done the trick.
Yet American androgyny proponents rarely refer to the kibbutz
experiment--for understandable reasons. Its failure--even if you
accept their own cultural explanation for it--puts a serious damper on
the idea of androgynizing America. In the U.S., after all, there's
nothing remotely approaching the level of commitment to surmounting
gender found among the early kibbutzniks. If androgyny proved
unattainable in a small socialist society whose citizens self-selected
for radical feminist convictions, how could one bring it about in
contemporary America, where most people don't want it? It would take a
massive amount of coercion--unacceptable in any democracy--to get us
even to the point where the kibbutzniks were when they failed to build
a post-gender society.
The best account of the experiment's breakdown, offered by
anthropologist Melford Spiro in his books Gender and Culture and
Children of the Kibbutz, points out an even bigger obstacle to
androgyny. Ultimately, Spiro argues, the kibbutzniks didn't succeed
because the mothers wanted their kids back. They wanted to take care
of their young children in the old-fashioned way, themselves. Two
hours a day with their kids wasn't enough. Even among the kibbutz
founders, Spiro notes, women often agonized over the sacrifice of
maternal pleasure that their egalitarian ideology demanded. He quotes
from one mother's autobiography: "Is it right to make the child return
for the night to the children's home, to say goodnight to it and send
it back to sleep among the fifteen or twenty others? This parting from
the child before sleep is so unjust!" Such feelings persisted and
intensified, until collective pressure forced the kibbutz to let
parents spend extra time with their kids.
Spiro holds that a pre-cultural form of maternal instinct subverted
the kibbutz's child-rearing approach. But a plausible cultural
explanation is even more devastating to feminist hopes for a
gender-free America. What really defeated androgyny on the kibbutz,
this interpretation posits, was the profound tension built in to the
very culture of modern democratic individualism that the kibbutzniks
embraced--the tension between liberty and equality. As part of their
insistence on their unique individuality, the kibbutzniks recognized
the unabridgeable unique individuality of everyone else. Hence, their
insistence on radical equality. Full equality meant that everyone had
to treat everyone else the same way. Even the differences between my
children and the neighbors' kids would have to go. They pretended that
their children belonged to the collective--"child of the kibbutz,"
they would say, not "my child."
But the other side of democratic individualism is the idea that each
of us is uniquely individual. And inseparable from this individualism
are certain aspirations--to express yourself personally, and to treat
yourself, your possessions, and your family differently from how you
treat everyone else. Child rearing doesn't escape these aspirations.
In fact, in modern societies people pay far greater attention to the
unique characters of their children than people do in traditional,
group-oriented societies. Lavishing intense, personal attention on
their kids is a favorite way for modern individuals to exercise
personal liberty.
Kibbutz mothers who hoped to treat everyone the same thus also wanted
to express their individual characters by molding their own kids. The
two goals--reflecting the two sides of modern democratic
individualism--were finally incommensurable. Eventually, the desire
for personal expression trumped the quest for radical equality. The
parents decided to raise their own kids in their own way. No one ever
got the chance to find out if further tinkering might have eliminated
their children's gender differences.
The culture of democratic individualism characterizes contemporary
America, too, of course, and it still cuts two ways. Feminists insist
on radical equality, and androgyny is the logical outcome of that
drive for equality. Yet at the same time, especially since the baby
boomers came on the scene, many American women have treated the
experience of motherhood as an exercise in self-expression--indeed,
they do so more fervently than the kibbutzniks.
A modern, self-expressive, committed-to-full-equality American mother
might know that her child is getting quality care from a relative, a
nanny, or a nursery, but she'll often feel dissatisfied, since the
care isn't hers. Part of the point of being a parent, she'll feel, is
to express one's unique personality through how one cares for and
shapes one's children. In practical terms, she'll be reluctant to give
up her kids long enough to break the cycle of "gender reproduction."
True, the last 40 years have seen tremendous changes in the social
roles of men and women--changes that could never have happened were
there not significant flexibility in gender roles. From the standpoint
of feminism's ideal of androgyny, though, the shift is still very
partial. Until the link between women and child rearing completely
breaks down, neither corporate boardrooms nor Harvard professorships
of mathematics will see numerical parity between men and women. In the
meantime, in disproportionate numbers, at critical points in their
careers, women will continue to choose mothering over professional
work.
From either a biological or cultural point of view, then, the feminist
project of androgyny is ultimately doomed. But that doesn't mean that
it can't do harm in the meantime. In America, many boys are slipping
behind in school; their sisters are significantly more likely to go on
to college. Yet thanks largely to the influence of academic feminists,
legal and educational resources still flow disproportionately to
supposedly victimized girls. In the end, gender won't disappear,
whatever the mavens of women's studies hope, but the careers of some
bright young men probably will.
Even if the differences are cultural, rather than biological, they are
ineradicable.
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list