[Paleopsych] Virginia Law Review: Dwight Lee: Symposium on the Theory of Public Choice
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Sun Oct 2 20:21:01 UTC 2005
Symposium on the Theory of Public Choice: Politics, Ideology, and the Power of
Public Choice
Virginia Law Review
MARCH, 1988
74 Va. L. Rev. 191
Dwight R. Lee *
* Professor of Economics and holder of the Ramsey Chair of Private Enterprise
Economics, University of Georgia.
SUMMARY:
... THE major strength of public choice derives from the assumption that
individuals, regardless of the decisionmaking environment, are motivated
primarily by private interests rather than the public interest. ... According
to this view, the private interest assumption misses the very essence of
political decision-making and renders public choice largely irrelevant to an
understanding of the political process. ... Critics of the private interest
assumption buttress their criticism by pointing to numerous studies that
indicate that people commonly vote against their economic interests in support
of broad ideological concerns. ... The key to the public choice explanation for
the importance of ideology in voting is found in the indecisiveness of the
individual vote, and the willingness to vote despite this indecisiveness. ...
If affecting the outcome of an election were the only benefit an individual
could derive from voting, it would be difficult to explain why people vote in
the numbers they do. ... The fact that people vote against their economic
interest in order to support positions of which they approve for ideological
reasons is hardly an embarrassment to public choice theorists. ... Thus, if the
voter receives any ideological satisfaction from voting yes, he might as well
do so; it will not cost him anything even if the legislation is detrimental to
his economic interest. ...
-----------
[*191] THE major strength of public choice derives from the assumption that
individuals, regardless of the decisionmaking environment, are motivated
primarily by private interests rather than the public interest. Economists have
long applied this assumption with considerable success to the analysis of
market behavior. By applying the private interest assumption to political
behavior, public choice economists have been able to use the analytical
leverage of economic theory to develop new insights into the operation of the
political process.
At the same time, critics attack the private interest assumption of public
choice. Economics has always attracted criticism on the ground that, even in
market settings, individuals are motivated by concerns broader than their
private interests. Few deny, however, that private interest is the dominant
motive in most market choices; when investigating traditional economic behavior
the private interest assumption is widely, if sometimes grudgingly, accepted as
a simplification justified by its explanatory power. There is greater
resistance to the assumption of private interest as the dominant motive in
political activity.
Most academics (including most economists) whose work concerns government
policy and practice tend to assume, if only implicitly, that political
decisionmakers are motivated by the desire to promote the interest of the
general community. As stated by political scientist Steven Kelman: "There is
the elementary fact that political decisions apply to the entire community.
That they do so encourages people to think about others when taking a stand.
This is in contrast to making personal decisions, when people think mainly of
themselves." 1 According to this view, the private interest assumption misses
the very essence of political decision-making [*192] and renders public choice
largely irrelevant to an understanding of the political process. 2
Critics of the private interest assumption buttress their criticism by pointing
to numerous studies that indicate that people commonly vote against their
economic interests in support of broad ideological concerns. 3 Furthermore, the
fact that people bother to vote at all is seen as evidence that in a political
setting individuals put their civic responsibility ahead of their private
interests. If, as public choice economists argue, an individual vote is
unlikely to affect the outcome of an election, then why would a person
motivated primarily by self-interest bother to vote at all?
The purpose of this Article is not to deny that individuals commonly vote on
the basis of ideology and against their economic interests, or that individuals
will take the trouble to vote, even though they recognize that their vote will
surely not affect the outcome of the election. These are obvious facts of
political life, and in no way are they inconsistent with public choice analysis
or with the private interest assumption that underlies this analysis. Indeed,
public choice better explains ideological voting than do the critics who point
to ideological voting in an attempt to discredit public choice. The key to the
public choice explanation for the importance of ideology in voting is found in
the indecisiveness of the individual vote, and the willingness to vote despite
this indecisiveness.
Parts I and II of this Article present a public choice explanation for the
importance of ideology voting. Although the input of voters influences
political outcomes, it does not necessarily control those outcomes. The
concerns of voters interact with the concerns of organized interest groups to
shape legislation. Part III discusses the effect that this interaction has on
the ideological content of political decisions.
[*193] I. VOTING AND THE LOW COST OF IDEOLOGICAL EXPRESSION
That large numbers of people vote is an empirical fact that cannot be denied.
But why do they do so? People do not go to the polls to vote for one candidate
over another for the same reason they go to the supermarket to choose one
product over another. In the supermarket an individual's product choice is
decisive; the individual receives the product he chooses because he chose it.
The motivation for making choices in the supermarket is dominated by outcome
considerations. This is not the case at the polls. The probability that an
individual's vote will be decisive in a typical election is effectively zero.
An individual may or may not receive the political outcome she favors, but not
because she voted for it. The outcome will be the same whether she votes yea,
nay, or not at all. The expectation of affecting the outcome has little to do
with an individual's motivation to vote.
If affecting the outcome of an election were the only benefit an individual
could derive from voting, it would be difficult to explain why people vote in
the numbers they do. But people receive satisfaction from participating in
processes they feel are important, from supporting things they believe are
good, and from opposing things they believe are bad. People are motivated to go
to the polls and vote for much the same reason they are motivated to go to the
sports arena and cheer. It is the satisfaction that comes from participation
and expression, not the expectation that they will determine the outcome, that
draws people to the polls and to the sports arena. There is no more difficulty
reconciling voting with private interest than there is with reconciling
attendance at sporting events with private interest.
Of course, any activity can be reconciled with private interest by inserting it
into the decisionmakers' utility function as a positively valued variable. The
obvious criticism of this reconciliation is that the theory that explains
everything explains nothing. For example, according to Professors Daniel Farber
and Philip Frickey, "Attempts have been made to reconcile voter behavior with
the economic model by postulating a 'taste' for voting. This explanation is
tautological -- anything people do can be 'justified' by saying they have a
taste for doing it." 4
[*194] This criticism notwithstanding, it is obvious that people place
positive value on a multitude of things, including participation and
expression, and public choice theory is not rendered less useful by
acknowledging this fact. Public choice assumes, as does economic theory in
general, that, no matter what their objectives, people pursue them rationally.
They will allocate their limited resources over alternative activities in order
to maximize their personal satisfaction. This assumption moves the analysis
beyond the level of a meaningless tautology that says nothing more than "people
do those things that they want to do."
The general implication of economic analysis is that if the cost of engaging in
an activity goes up, people will engage in it less, and vice versa. Applied to
politics, the analysis implies that people will behave differently in a
political setting than in a market setting because the relative costs of
alternative choices are different. This allows behavioral predictions to be
made on the basis of objective differences between political and market
institutions, and between the incentives they generate. Methodological
consistency is therefore possible when evaluating and contrasting differences
in political and market behavior.
In particular, there is no need to resort to the assumption that people are
more concerned with the public interest when making political choises than when
making market choices in order to explain the importance of ideology in
political behavior. Indeed, by applying the private interest assumption
uniformly over both decisionmaking settings, public choice provides an
evenhanded explanation of why ideological considerations are more important in
political decisions than in market decisions. The fact that people vote against
their economic interest in order to support positions of which they approve for
ideological reasons is hardly an embarrassment to public choice theorists. To
the contrary, the ability to provide a coherent explanation for ideological
voting illustrates the power of public choice.
People put ideological considerations ahead of economic interests when voting
for the simple reason that it costs them almost nothing to do so. Consider the
situation facing an individual who is contemplating a vote for expensive
environmental protection legislation, or for a candidate who pledges support
for the legislation. On the one hand, the individual may feel that it is
important to protect the natural environment, not only for himself but for
[*195] others as well, and will feel a sense of moral virtue by voting for the
legislation. On the other hand, he will realize that the legislation, if
enacted, will impose costs on him in the form of higher prices and taxes. The
voter can ignore these costs with impunity, however, because his vote will,
with near certainty, make no difference as to whether or not the legislation is
enacted. Thus, if the voter receives any ideological satisfaction from voting
yes, he might as well do so; it will not cost him anything even if the
legislation is detrimental to his economic interest. 5
This situation contrasts sharply with that faced by decisionmakers in a market
setting. It is possible for consumers to seek goods produced by firms that
incur the necessary costs of minimizing the negative environmental impact of
their productive processes. If enough consumers expressed their ideological
commitments to a clean environment in this way, it would pay firms to invest
voluntarily in pollution abatement until, at the margin, the value from a
cleaner environment equaled the cost of acquiring it, as reflected in higher
product prices. But this is not an effective approach to environmental
protection, because few individuals will buy more expensive products, when less
expensive products are available, in order to reduce environmental pollution.
To act on the basis of ideological considerations by choosing the more
expensive products is costly because, as opposed to voting, the individual's
choices in the marketplace are decisive. The demand curve for ideological
expression is like all demand curves: greater costs result in less quantity
demanded. Not surprisingly, then, ideology plays a minor role in market
decisions and a major role in voting decisions.
II. SPECIAL INTEREST INFLUENCE AND THE HIGH COST OF IDEOLOGICAL EXPRESSION
Although voters may make decisions predominantly on the basis of ideological
considerations, the outcomes that emerge from the [*196] political process will
reflect other considerations as well. Not all political actors will elevate
ideology to a dominant role, for the simple reason that for some it is more
costly to do so than it is for the individual voter. Special interest groups
typically organize around narrowly motivated economic concerns, with little
regard for ideological considerations. 6 This is to be expected, given the fact
that organized groups are often able to exert decisive influence over political
decisions. For an organized group to use this influence to promote an
ideologically motivated outcome detrimental to its economic interest would be
genuinely costly. 7
The clear implication is that the influence of politically organized groups
will reduce the ideological content of political decisions. Public choice
analysis suggests, however, that this occurs in ways that are not always
obvious to the casual observer. Organized interests will have less influence on
the general nature of the legislation that is passed than they will on the
detailed implementation and enforcement of that legislation. 8
Consider, for example, the previous discussion of the costlessness of
expressing concern for the environment by voting for an environmental
protection program. The result is strong electoral, and therefore legislative,
support for such programs that has little to do with special interest
influence. But after an individual makes a costless expression of support for
environmental protection at the polls, much remains to be done if the
environment is to be protected adequately. It is unfortunately costly for an
individual to express concern for environmental quality by lobbying for the
most [*197] efficient environmental protection programs and by monitoring
those who implement these programs. Predictably, there is little genuine public
surveillance of environmental protection programs, and organized groups have
significant latitude to influence environmental programs in ways that serve
their private interests. This means, of course, that these programs are far
less effective at protecting the environment than they could be. 9
Organized groups often do little to oppose legislation that is potentially
adverse to their interests, especially when public opinion strongly favors the
legislation. Well-organized groups often will "get on board" and "support"
legislation that is inimical to their economic interests. But, as opposed to
individuals who voted for the legislation and who quickly forgot it once it was
passed, the affected organized interests will be unrelenting in their efforts
to influence the day-to-day details of the legislation's implementation. This
influence will typically not be exerted on behalf of the broad public interest.
Government attempts to help the poor, protect the consumer, and regulate
business pricing and practices provide additional examples of supposedly
general interest legislation that is subverted by organized interest groups.
The initial motivation for the legislation may have been dominated by
ideological considerations, but narrow economic concerns motivate the special
interest influence that does so much to determine its effect.
III. CONCLUSION
As critics of public choice are so fond of pointing out, ideological
considerations are important in political decisionmaking. But, contrary to the
criticism, the importance of ideology in politics is completely consistent with
public choice analysis. Indeed, the power of public choice analysis is
demonstrated by its ability to explain why ideology is more important in
political choices than in market choices, without resorting to an ad hoc
bifurcation of underlying [*198] motivations. Public choice assumes that an
individual making a political decision is fundamentally the same as one making
a market decision. The explanation for the difference in the ideological
content of these decisions is found in the differences between political and
market institutions, and in the effect these differences have on the costs of
alternative choices. It is simply less costly for people to base decisions on
ideological considerations in a political setting than in a market setting.
The public choice approach does more, however, than explain why ideology is
more important in political behavior than in market behavior. The cost of
ideological decisionmaking varies over different political settings, and the
ideological content of political decisions varies accordingly. Ideological
conviction and narrow economic interest interact in interesting ways to
determine political outcomes, and public choice provides a methodologically
consistent way of analyzing this interaction. In particular, public choice
suggests that ideology will be more important than narrow economic interest in
providing general direction to legislation, but less important in determining
the details of the legislation and how it is implemented.
Public choice provides only one window through which to view the political
process. Any serious attempt to understand political phenomena requires the
view from many windows. But public choice provides a far better perspective on
the role of ideology in politics than many of its critics seem to realize.
FOOTNOTES:
n1 S. Kelman, Making Public Policy: A Hopeful View of American Government 22
(1987).
n2 Critics of public choice do not deny that private interest is a powerful
motive, but rather argue that public choice overstates its influence over
political behavior: "Instead of trying to mix self-interest and altruism into
every decision, the individual might try to reserve certain decisions to
self-interest and others to altruism." Id. at 244. Steven Kelman leaves no
doubt that people tend to give the greatest weight, or "pride of place," to
altruism in political decisions. Id.
n3 For citation and discussion of many of these studies, see, e.g., id. at
255-59; S. Rhoades, The Economist's View of the World: Government, Markets, and
Public Policy 153-58 (1985); Farber & Frickey, The Jurisprudence of Public
Choice, 65 Tex. L. Rev. 873, 897-900 (1987).
n4 Farber & Frickey, supra note 3, at 894 n.129.
n5 Tullock used the indecisiveness of individual votes to explain why people
vote for poverty programs that, if passed, will cost them far more than they
would contribute voluntarily. Tullock, The Charity of the Uncharitable, 9 W.
Econ. J. 379 (1971). For discussions of the implications of the indecisiveness
of an individual vote, see Brennan & Buchanan, Voter Choice: Evaluating
Political Alternatives, 28 Am. Behav. Scientist 185 (1984); Brennan & Lomasky,
The Impartial Spectator Goes to Washington, 1 Econ. Phil. 189 (1985).
n6 Some politically active interest groups are organized around ideological
issues for largely ideological reasons. However, most politically organized
interest groups, certainly most well-financed interest groups, are motivated
primarily by narrow economic concerns.
n7 The standard explanation for political interest groups' focus on narrow
economic interests is that it is easier to organize a group around such
interests. See M. Olson, The Logic of Collective Action 142-45 (1965). The
argument of this Article is that once a group becomes politically influential,
no matter what the initial impetus behind its organization, it is costly for it
to ignore private economic concerns in order to advance an ideologically
motivated agenda.
n8 Based on studies of the legislative impact of organized interest groups,
some investigators have concluded that these groups have relatively little
influence. See, e.g., R. Bauer, I. Pool & L. Dexter, American Business and
Public Policy 341-49 (1963). However, the studies underlying this conclusion
are flawed because they were concerned almost exclusively with whether Congress
passes legislation the interest groups favor, and gave little attention to how
these groups influence the details of legislation that is passed. See K.
Schlozman & J. Tierney, Organized Interests and American Democracy 8 (1986).
n9 There is compelling evidence that pollution control policy is less effective
than it could be. See R. Crandall, H. Gruenspecht, T. Keeler & L. Lave,
Regulating the Automobile 85-116 (1986); A. Kneese & C. Schultze, Pollution,
Prices, & Public Policy (1975). There is also compelling evidence that the
deficiencies in pollution control policy are in large measure the result of
special interest influence. See J. Thomasian, The Clean Air Act, the Electric
Utilities, and the Coal Market (1982); Bureaucracy vs. Environment: The
Environmental Costs of Bureaucratic Governance (J. Baden & R. Stroup eds.
1981); Ackerman & Hassler, Beyond the New Deal: Coal and the Clean Air Act, 89
Yale L.J. 1466, 1497-1511 (1980).
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list