[Paleopsych] Guardian: I'm not guilty - but my brain is
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Mon Aug 23 15:11:49 UTC 2004
I'm not guilty - but my brain is
http://education.guardian.co.uk/print/0,3858,4990893-110865,00.html
A leading neuroscientist caused a sensation by claiming crimes are the
result of brain abnormalities. Laura Spinney investigates a slanging
match between scientists and philosophers
Laura Spinney
Thursday August 12, 2004
Last month, the case against Patrizia Reggiani was reopened in Italy.
She is serving a 26-year jail sentence for having ordered the killing
of her husband, the fashion supremo Maurizio Gucci. At the first trial
in 1998, expert witnesses dismissed her lawyers' claims that surgery
for a brain tumour had changed her personality. The new trial has been
granted because her lawyers believe that brain imaging techniques
developed since then will reveal damage that was previously
undetectable, and strengthen their case for an acquittal.
The idea that someone should not be punished if their abnormal neural
make-up leaves them no choice but to break the law is contentious but
not new. However, one prominent neuroscientist has sparked a storm by
picking it up and turning it round. Writing in the Frankfurter
Allgemeine Zeitung, one of Germany's leading newspapers, Wolf Singer
argued that crime itself should be taken as evidence of brain
abnormality, even if no abnormality can be found, and criminals
treated as incapable of having acted otherwise.
His claims have brought howls of outrage from academics across the
sciences and humanities. But Singer counters that the idea is nothing
but a natural extension of the thesis that free will is an illusion -
a theory that he feels is supported by decades of work in
neuroscience.
The head of the Max Planck Institute for Brain Research in Frankfurt,
Singer is best known for his work on the so-called binding problem of
perception. This is the conundrum of how we perceive an object as an
integrated whole, when we know that the brain processes the various
elements of it - colours, angles, and so on - separately. His group
was among the first to suggest, and then demonstrate, that the answer
lay in the synchronisation encoding the separate features. He has
since extrapolated those ideas to the process by which we make
decisions, which has led him to question whether we are really the
free-acting agents we imagine ourselves to be.
His argument goes like this. Neurobiology tells us that there is no
centre in the brain where actions are planned and decisions made.
Decisions emerge from a collection of dynamic systems that run in
parallel and are underpinned by nerve cells that talk to each other -
the brain. If you look back in evolution to say, the sea slug Aplysia,
you see that the building blocks of this brain have not changed. The
amino acids, the nerve cells, the signalling pathways and largely the
genes, are the same. "It's the same material [in humans], just more
complex," says Singer. "So the same rules must govern what humans do.
Unavoidable conclusion."
He argues that the human brain has to be complex to compute all the
myriad variables that influence each decision we make - genetic
factors, socially learned factors, momentary triggers including
commands and wishes, to name a few. And because it considers most of
those variables at a subconscious level, we are not aware of all the
factors that make us behave in a certain way, just as we are not aware
of all the elements of an object that are processed separately by our
visual brains. As humans, however, we are able to extract some of
those factors and make them the focus of attention; that is, render
them conscious. And with our behaviour, as with the world we see, we
yearn to build a coherent picture. So we might justify our decisions
in ways that have nothing to do with our real, subconscious
motivations.
The most striking example of this is hypnotism. Singer himself learned
how to hypnotise while a student at Cambridge University. At a party,
he instructed a Royal Air Force pilot to remove the bulb from a light
fitting and place it in a flowerpot, on hearing the word Germany. The
pilot did so in mid-conversation, much to the amusement of the
onlookers. They were amateurs, they didn't debrief him properly. And
when they told him what he had done, because he had no recollection of
doing it, he was extremely disturbed.
According to Singer, what the pilot did is explained by the structure
of his brain and its inherent weakness, if you see it as a weakness to
be susceptible to hypnotism. The same goes for a murderer or a thief,
he says. We live in a society where people whose behaviour is
considered to deviate from the norm - as determined arbitrarily by
that society - answer to the justice system. But the way they are
treated by that system is, he believes, inconsistent.
If some abnormality is found in a person's brain, the doctor's report
is submitted as mitigating evidence and the defendant may be treated
more leniently. If nothing is discovered, they are not. Take the case
of the British man who terrorised 200 officials because he thought
they intended to have him sectioned under the Mental Health Act.
Psychiatrists found no sign of a mitigating mental illness, and he was
jailed for life. But, says Singer, if a person does something
antisocial, the reason for it is in the brain. The underlying cause
may be a twist in a gene, or a tiny hormonal imbalance that cannot be
detected with current technology. "It could have multiple reasons," he
says. "But these reasons must all manifest themselves in brain
architecture."
In practice, he says, the change in thinking he advocates wouldn't
change the way we treat criminals all that much. People considered a
danger to society should be kept away from society, re-educated as far
as possible and in cases where this is not possible, simply kept away,
as they already are. But he would like to see the courts place less
burden on psychiatrists, who are not capable of identifying all the
subtle structural changes that lead individuals to behave as they do.
"As long as we can't identify all the causes, which we cannot and will
probably never be able to do, we should grant that for everybody there
is a neurobiological reason for being abnormal," he says.
He does not argue that a criminal should not be held responsible for
their crime. After all, if a person is not responsible for their own
brain, who is? Neither does he argue that we should do away with
concepts of good and evil. "We judge our fellow men as either
conforming to our rules or breaking them," he says. "We need to
continue to assign values to our behaviour, because there is no other
way to organise society." However, he does argue that when people
commit crimes, they are not acting independently of the nerve cells
and amino acids that make up their brains, and that behave according
to certain deterministic principles.
One important implication of his argument is that treatment meted out
to offenders should be less about revenge and punishment, and more
about assessing their risk of re-offending, given the brain they have.
Of course, this already happens. If a woman has been driven to a crime
of passion after severe provocation, having otherwise lived an
exemplary life, she is considered less of a danger to society than a
man who has frequently abducted teenage girls, raped and murdered
them. Another corollary of Singer's ideas that he recognises will be
harder for people to swallow, is that the consequences of a crime
should be considered less important than they are, since an individual
can only control his own actions and not those of others. For example,
a driver seen running a red light should be treated the same way
whether or not he hit the child who, unseen from the wheel, stepped
into the road at the same moment.
"Breathtaking," is how Ted Honderich, a philosopher at University
College London, scathingly describes Singer's foray into traditional
philosophical territory. Honderich says philosophers have discussed
different definitions of freedom for centuries, one of which is
perfectly compatible with the sort of determinism Singer describes.
That is, if free action is defined as action caused by your character
- whatever hereditary and environmental influences contributed to that
character - then you are free even if your brain does resemble that of
a slug.
And although the discussion might appear to have degenerated into a
slanging match between scientists and philosophers, neuroscientists
have also criticised Singer. "We don't know enough to make such
conclusions," says Cornelius Weiller, an expert in brain imaging at
Hamburg University. Singer is right, he says, that there is no
homunculus in the brain, making our decisions for us. But the question
remains, how do all those parallel computations become integrated, and
how does the self feel that "I" made the decision? Science has yet to
answer the binding problem of decision-making.
In response to the accusation that he is rehashing old ideas, Singer
points out that the German newspaper debate got under way without him,
and he was merely responding. So the more interesting question,
perhaps, is why the public is interested again now. One reason, he
thinks, is that people look at their societies, see that the
totalitarian ones failed, and realise that the most complex are
self-organising and impossible to steer or control. "You free yourself
from authorities, including the gods, but you find yourself part of an
evolving system," he says. "Now you realise that you don't really have
influence on the dynamics of the systems in which you are. I think
this gives a feeling of helplessness."
Further reading
· Keiner kann anders, als er ist, by Wolf Singer, Frankfurter
Allgemeine Zeitung, January 8 2004 (in German only; his original
essay)
· How Free Are You? The Determinism Problem, by Ted Honderich (Oxford
University Press, 2002) ISBN 0199251975
· The Volitional Brain: Towards a Neuroscience of Free Will, by
Benjamin Libet (ed) et al (Imprint Academic, 2000) ISBN 0907845509
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list