[Paleopsych] Independent Institute: The Case Against the Democratic State
Premise Checker
checker at panix.com
Tue Aug 24 22:27:16 UTC 2004
The Case Against the Democratic State
http://www.independent.org/publications/tir/article.asp?issueID=38&articleID=220
[28]VOLUME 9 NUMBER 1
SUMMER 2004
[ -Volume 9 Number 1 Summer 2004]
Title: The Case Against the Democratic State
Author: Gordon Graham
Published: Charlottesville, Va.: Imprint Academic
Price: [29]$17.90 (paperback)
Pages: 96
Reviewer: [30]James R. Otteson
Affiliation: University of Alabama
This slim volume is part of a publishing program called "Societas:
Essays in Moral and Cultural Criticism," which is advertised as an
attempt to revive the tradition of thoughtful political pamphleteering
that reached its zenith in seventeenth-century England. Its purpose is
for scholars to discuss important "moral" and "cultural" topics by
communicating with the educated lay public, not just with other
scholars. The editorial advisory board of the series includes figures
such as John Gray of the London School of Economics, and the five
volumes already published include two by Gordon Graham, one by Anthony
Freeman, one by Tibor Machan, and one by Graham Allen. Although the
advertisement's claim that "each book should take no more than an
evening to read" is a bit optimistic for Graham's Case Against the
Democratic State, certainly the book can be read over a weekend, and
in any event the series generally and this book in particular are
welcome additions to academic publishing on political and cultural
thought.
As befits the intention of this series, Graham's thesis can be put
simply: the arguments typically thought to justify democracy as the
best form of government in fact fail to justify it, and indeed some of
the central conceptual commitments that people assume support
democracy turn out to support far different sorts of government.
The book begins impressively: "The history of the last two hundred
years, at least in Europe, is a story of the immense and relentless
growth of one social institution at the expense of the others. I mean
the State" (p. 1). This declaration is a promising start for a several
reasons. First, it draws attention to a spectacular feature of human
social life in recent history, a feature that has been unaccountably
underinvestigated and even ignored by most political theorists.
Second, it asks the reader to pay attention to empirical matters, with
which many contemporary political theorists are too little concerned.
And third, it capitalizes the S in state. Graham retains his practice
of capitalizing that s throughout the book, subtly suggesting to the
reader that the state might be a single phenomenon with a single
central nature that, despite superficial variations, can itself be
investigated, analyzed, and understood.
Beginning the discussion in this way also introduces an ongoing theme
of Graham's book, which is that people's beliefs about political
matters are often riddled with misperceptions and even falsehoods.
This reality is reflected first and foremost, according to Graham, in
their misunderstanding of the true nature of the state. What is its
true nature? "I shall define its essential character in this way: the
State is the monopolist of legitimate coercion" (p. 6). Despite its
varied appearances, Graham argues, the state invariably has as its
essence the exclusive claim to use or threaten force. This nature of
the state thus immediately calls for an answer to a question rarely
raised among contemporary political theorists: Is a state justifiable
at all? Graham not only takes up this question but argues that most of
the arguments used to justify the state in fact fail.
It is not true, for example, that absent the state all social life
would be warfare, for, if it were so, then "the officers of the
State--i.e. the police--could do little to counteract this" because
the police would be unable to stop systematic inclinations toward
"anti-social" tendencies, no matter how many of them there were (p.
11). Here Graham might also have mentioned that an assumption of
systematic antisocial inclinations among human beings would also have
to include the police, who are after all human beings, too; hence,
asking the state to counteract such a tendency would not solve the
problem, but rather would only relocate it. Graham argues further that
it is simply not true that what prevents most individuals from acting
in an "antisocial" way is fear of punishment; instead, he contends,
most people prefer to act in ways that extend and strengthen sociality
rather than in ways that destroy it (p. 11). Moreover, in those few
cases "where trust breaks down," Graham claims, "recourse to
law--litigation--is a very imperfect remedy, and generally serves to
make matters worse" by encouraging people to view one another as
adversaries requiring legal accountably rather than as fellow human
beings whom we should trust until we have reason not to (p. 12).
Finally, Graham points out that "the existence of the State does not
put an end to criminal activity" (p. 12, emphasis in original). He
does not make the bolder if more contentious claim that state activity
itself constitutes "criminal activity"--that, for example, the state
lives on property stolen from citizens and on labor coercively
enforced (though he hints at such an argument on p. 19)--but rather he
offers the more straightforward point that no state, however "strong
and efficient," has ever completely eradicated "theft of property,
fraudulent transactions, kidnapping, violence against the person and
so on" (p. 12).
The latter point is instrumental in Graham's larger argument that when
engaging in political theorizing, one must keep one's nose to the
empirical grindstone. Imagined ideals are always going to be superior
to any actual state, so it is pointless and even dangerous to engage
in mere a priori reasoning about how one might ideally like the world
to be. One must look instead at possible alternatives and compare them
to one another. Proper political thought thus engages in "relative
judgement[s] between good and less good," which means that a judgment
about what system of political organization ought to be recommended
"must turn on empirical evidence on the balance of probabilities" (p.
13). This statement may seem like common sense, but it is in fact a
refreshing departure from the practice of most political philosophers,
who rarely avail themselves of actual historical and empirical
evidence and who in some cases expressly disdain reliance on actual
facts on the grounds that these facts might muddy the waters of
pristine a priori philosophy. Facts do have a way of muddying the
waters, but political thought by its nature concerns, or should
concern, actual human beings living in an actual world. Political
thought is not logic or mathematics, and human beings are not
disembodied rational intellects. Graham is right to insist that
political philosophy must deal with the real world, and his book is a
needed reminder of that requirement.
The bulk of Graham's book is aimed at making cases for three principal
claims: one, anarchism has much greater appeal philosophically than is
commonly thought, and the obvious objections to it fail (chap. 1);
two, the arguments typically adduced in support of democracy also fail
and indeed contribute to what Graham calls the "democratic myth"
(chaps. 2-4); and three, the best of the realizable forms of
government might turn out to be a kind of republicanism (chap. 6).
Graham's discussions are engaging and thought provoking, and they
contain a number of interesting insights. Especially useful is his
undermining of the idea that democracy is justified because it rests
on the consent of the governed. Citizens of a democratic society
cannot be said to have consented to their state and to what it does
because, Graham argues, voting actually has no causal efficacy (chaps.
3 and 4). His sobering claim is that no single person's vote ever
determines or affects the outcome of an election, so if voting is to
have any purpose at all for a person, that purpose cannot be to elect
or remove any candidate. This point alone goes some way toward making
the case against the democratic state.
I have a few quibbles with some of Graham's claims, but I mention here
only two worries about a single suggestion he makes. When discussing
"alternatives to democracy," Graham recommends republicanism, which he
defines somewhat idiosyncratically as "any form of government in which
the political system works in such a way that serious constraints are
put on the use of State power" (p. 84). He argues plausibly that this
definition is preferable to other, more common definitions of
republicanism because it focuses on what really is important about
states--namely, "how political systems work in practice and not how
their constitutions say they ought to" (p. 85). On his view, it does
not matter whether a state is officially "democratic," "monarchical,"
and so on, or whether state power is constrained "institutionally";
what matters is whether limitations on state power are "realized,"
regardless of how (p. 85). Although this way of thinking papers over
some issues, the distinction between institutional and realized
limitations nevertheless has considerable merit. The annually released
report Economic Freedom of the World, by James Gwartney and Robert
Lawson (Washington, D.C.: Cato Institute), presents evidence that
supports the notion that what matters is what policies are actually in
place, not what is officially espoused.
The first question I have about Graham's discussion of republicanism
and alternatives to democracy, however, is, Why did he not reconsider
here the anarchism for which he argued earlier in the book? Why not
simply argue that no state can be legitimate--period? In the first
chapter, Graham accepts a Hobbesian argument that the state is
necessary to solve prisoners' dilemma-style coordination problems, but
the work of writers such as Robert Axelrod and Bruce Benson, among
many others, has suggested that a coercive state in fact is not
necessary to solve those problems. Graham unfortunately does not
mention these arguments. The case for his republicanism would have
been stronger had he done so.
The other worry is that Graham's republicanism is liable to the same
or at least to some of the same objections that Graham raises to
democracy. As mentioned earlier, one part of the "democratic myth,"
Graham argues, is that voting in a democracy actually gives people
some say. Graham correctly points out that "the belief that elections
give power to the people is an illusion. There is no coherent
conception of action and will that can show `the people,' either
individually or collectively, to be choosing a government, or throwing
one out of office when they cast their votes" (p. 86). By contrast, he
claims, his republicanism not only allows the electoral process to
"disperse" power (p. 87), but also gives voting an "expressive" if not
a "causal" purpose (p. 89). The argument here is somewhat opaque. If
voting in a "democratic" government is pointless because no person's
vote has any causal efficacy, then it would seem that the same point
applies to voting under a Grahamsian republican government, even if in
the latter case the intent is to "disperse" power rather than to
concentrate it. The capacity to disperse power would seem to require
causal efficacy as much as the capacity to concentrate it does.
Moreover, it is not clear exactly what "expressive" ends voting really
serves. Perhaps officially it is claimed to show patriotism or
solidarity or community, but Graham has asked us to pay attention to
actual effects, not aspirations. From this perspective, it would
appear that if voting has any function at all, it is to give some
people power over others, precisely what Graham hopes to avoid.
One suspects that in a longer book Graham would have provided cogent
responses to these questions, but The Case Against the Democratic
State is not intended to be a comprehensive treatise. Rather, it is an
invitation to think harder about such matters than most people are
commonly inclined to think. The student, the intelligent layman, and
even--perhaps especially--most academic specialists would profit
greatly from encountering arguments that plausibly question widespread
political pieties and that introduce empirical investigation where it
is clearly appropriate. Graham's little book is an excellent candidate
for inclusion on an undergraduate syllabus or on the reading list of
anyone wondering what exactly the nearly universal prejudice in favor
of democracy is actually based upon.
James R. Otteson
University of Alabama
References
30. http://www.independent.org/aboutus/person_detail.asp?id=589
31. http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/ASIN/090784538X/theindepeende-20
32. http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/ASIN/090784538X/theindepeende-20
More information about the paleopsych
mailing list